From
Elias Mandala's, "Beyond the 'Crisis' in African Food Studies"
The
Ethiopian and Sahelian famines of the 1970s and 1980s, and the publicity
surrounding them, generated new scholarly interest in food matters. The
disasters attracted the attention of young people looking for dissertation
topics, and encouraged older specialists in rural and development studies
to re-examine their research findings and assumptions in light of the problem.
Africa's agricultural and agrarian history thus witnessed a rush to relevance.
Every annual meeting of the African Studies Association (ASA) featured
many sessions dedicated to the problem. But concern for relevance in the
midst of "crisis" also exposed the limits of historical research not firmly
grounded in the specific cultural and historical reality of the world of
African peasants. Thus, neither those who made the predictions about the
looming disaster nor their students have pursued the story beyond the 1980s.
Few spoke of hunger in the 1990s and even fewer in the twenty-first century.
Only one panel¾out of about 300¾at the 2002 annual meeting
of the ASA was specifically devoted to food matters, and the June 2003
annual congress of the Association of African Political Scientists offered
no section dedicated to the subject. These scholars met nowhere else but
in Southern Africa, where ordinary people were not talking about "development"¾the
over-riding theme of the congress (whatever that means)¾but about
hunger. Southern Africa's recent food shortages caught the academic world
sleeping, for reasons I will presently show.
This
essay identifies two main streams of thought in the debates of the 1970s
and 1980s, which I call the "crisis literature," for they were preoccupied
with sudden and dramatic scarcity. The first gives priority to environmental
factors in the etiology of famine, directing our attention to natural conditions
such as soil structures, rainfall patterns, and climatic variability. Liberals
reject environmental determinism and propose to understand Africa's food
deficits in political, social, and economic terms. Instead of engaging
the crisis literature by invoking the authority of Marx, Malthus, and other
big guns in the pantheon of post-industrial philosophies, this study turns
to peasants whose knowledge about the problem rests on their lived experiences
as food producers, consumers, and victims of hunger. They have developed
not only sophisticated agricultural systems, but also ideas that seek to
make sense of this important aspect of their lives. Above all, they make
and implement the decisions that determine the indigenous food supply on
a daily and seasonal basis.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
John Higginson's, "Making Short Work of Traditions: State Terror and Collective
Violence in South Africa"
It
is impossible to make much sense of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission
(TRC) unless one ties it to the political settlement arrived at between
1990 and 1993 and its most palpable institutional expression, the TNE,
which grew out of the miscarried reforms of the closing phases of apartheid.
The arrangement created a situation in which the white power structure,
backed up by the army and security forces, was unable to suppress black
opposition. Meanwhile black opposition and the other forces arrayed against
apartheid
did not have the immediate capacity to overthrow the state-hence the negotiated
settlement. But even the most generous understanding of "negotiated settlement"
failed to touch on how subordinate groups would gain access to socioeconomic
resources, whether aggregate income would be distributed in a more democratic
fashion, and how living conditions and access to education would be enhanced
for the black majority. Also, the distance between disclosure of the state's
atrocities and justice continued to be substantial.
The
testimony and proceedings of the South African TRC are voluminous and instructive.
They mark the first time in modern South Africa's history that an official
body has encouraged people to speak freely about recent events and to speculate
about how the violent excesses of the past might instruct the creation
of a better, more democratic society. It may also mark one of the first
times a modern state has frankly admitted that the prerequisites of a truly
just society do not already exist. These frank admissions have encouraged
discrete groups of people to assume a certain smugness about the authoritarian
single-mindedness of the apartheid and segregation eras. Much like people
of another time who admired Mussolini and the Italian fascists because
they appeared to make Italy's trains run on time, some in South Africa
still believe that a measure of commonplace virtue existed in the certainties
of South Africa's previous forms of social engineering. Political virtue,
however, is never commonplace. It requires more courage than force to maintain,
and it demands a degree of skepticism about motives, interests, and outcomes
that authoritarian governments find disturbing. Skepticism soon became
the hallmark of the TRC, which aimed to establish a process for democratic
procedure in which sustained inquiry about motives and intent would be
focused on the former South African state and its opponents. But could
such a high-minded charge hold up under wide-ranging and numerous accounts
of atrocities and state terror?
I
propose to examine how the testimony of ordinary South African witnesses
from the former districts of Marico and Rustenburg, and also from the fictional
political convention of Bophuthatswana, enabled the TRC to pursue its expanded
charge of "establishing as a complete a picture as possible of the causes,
nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights which were committed
during the period from 1 March 1960, including the antecedents, circumstances,
factors and context of such violations.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Hugh Ragsdale's, "Comparative Historiography of European Revolutions"
The
historiography of the Russian Revolution differs from that of its two predecessors
in a variety of ways. Most obviously, the Russian is the only one that
collapsed under the observation of historians currently writing about it,
which must have influenced their views. The Russian Revolution-cause
célèbre or écrasez l'infâme-is now a lost
cause, and yet, no Russian Restoration has occurred. Thus historians lack
the long-term perspective we enjoy on the other two revolutions, and the
very immediacy of the phenomenon means we have yet to achieve emotional
distance.
The
Soviet collapse has gratified conservative historians, discomfited left-leaning
social historians, and influenced their writing. The collapse itself necessarily
damaged the legitimacy of the regime and raised doubts about the very viability
of Marxism, and historical writing has necessarily been concerned with
uncovering the sources of Marxism's illegitimacy and lack of viability
from its very beginnings. Improved access to archival sources and their
aggressive exploration by native Russian historians-Afanas'ev, Seliunin,
Tsipko, Volkogonov, and Zubkova, among others-have rendered the aggressive
initiative and notorious brutality of the Soviet regime ever more difficult
to ignore and, at least in the early post-Soviet days, elicited a vocal
native disapproval of the record of Soviet government that had never been
possible until the Gorbachev era. These phenomena have unavoidably influenced
our Western colleagues as well. Thus a considerable, though not unanimous,
retreat from the radical positions of historical interpretation on the
part of many of the social historians/revisionists has occurred in the
wake of the Soviet debacle. While a genuine convergence of the American
and Soviet systems that Brzezinski and Huntington foresaw never took place,
the views of the social historians and their old enemies, the predominantly
political historians, have-awkwardly and with difficulty, perhaps-conspicuously
converged.
Political
affinities open fissures among historians and define conflicting interpretations
to all these revolutions, and so inevitably does the passing of generations.
As Peter Lake wrote of the changing fashions in the historiography of the
English Revolution, "We are surely dealing here only with another revolution
of the wheel of historiographical fortune of the sort produced by the institutionalized
need for novelty of interpretation among professional historians." Each
generation of historians revises history in pursuit of originality, as
our academic criteria require us to do-to finish the dissertation, to acquire
tenure and promotion, and to avoid the excessive aping of the preceding
generation. As Gypsy Rose Lee put it, you gotta have a gimmick, and though
hers is not literally shared by our profession, we do stubbornly strip
the preceding generations of their academic dress in the natural drive
for innovation and originality, none of which necessarily corresponds constructively
to the criteria of professional or disciplinary integrity. The pursuit
of fashion or the flight from convention in a discipline whose charge is
the preservation of tradition threatens now and then to drive historical
writing ever farther from what the common reader can recognize as history.
When one abstraction has been extracted from another, which was similarly
lifted from yet another, and so on, the end result may have some charm
for dabblers in word babble, but it amounts to little more than esoteric
periphrasis. The medium, or methodology, becomes the message. As Robert
V. Daniels recently put it, "No truth is solid and everything depends on
the imagination if not the whim of the observer. History is 'constructed,'
not discovered. At best this means a skeptical relativism, at worst a free
hand to subordinate history to political agendas."
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
David F. Krein's, "Birth Dates Matter: Generational Voting in the British
House of Commons, 1841-1859"
Is
there such a thing as generational behavior? It would seem so, or at least
generational analysis has existed since the earliest of times. From the
Old Testament to Homer, from Herodotus to Thucydides, from Hesiod to Philo
to Polybius, attempts to explain human activity have turned to the concept
of the social, as distinct from the familial or demographic, generation.
Every generation seems to produce thinkers who play with the idea, perhaps
because generational behavior appears instinctive and rooted in the human
unconscious. Generally, these efforts at understanding have emerged sporadically,
even fitfully, although the twentieth century produced more systematic
and sophisticated versions of them.
Contributions
to generational analysis include Karl Mannheim's work on generational social
conditioning, and Ortega y Gasset's focus on the generational "group mind,"
followed by his student Julian Marias' work on generations and historical
methods. Anthony Esler provided a convincing argument for historians' use
of generational analysis, while Alan Spitzer presented a thoughtful treatment
of its problems and possibilities. And a decade ago, William Strauss and
Neil Howe introduced an overarching theory that linked four recurring generations
to a repetitive four-fold historical cyclical process similar to the Etruscan
Saeculum.
A
general consensus seems to have emerged among those who work with historical
generations: they do exist; they are shaped by experiences shared as children
and young adults; and history makes generations and generations make history.
Yet, much of the evidence adduced for this consensus has been impressionistic,
which raises the question, can generational behavior be empirically demonstrated?
My work with voting records in the British House of Commons in the 1840s
and 1850s strongly suggests that it can be.
The
possibility of an empirical demonstration first struck me when I ran a
test on the data I had already accumulated on the British Reformed House
of Commons to see if voting behavior differed by age. I had already organized
all the Parliaments and their personnel from 1833 to 1868, recording their
votes on various issues, including the three divisions on the Corn Laws
in 1846, so it was a simple matter to graph these votes by the year of
birth of the members voting. To my surprise, supporters of the Corn Laws,
which were protective tariffs on imported grain, appeared significantly
younger than those who supported Free Trade and other tests persuaded me
to investigate further.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Doyne Dawson's, "The Assault on Eurocentric History"
In
recent years, "Eurocentricity" has come to mean, not the undeniable fact
that the modern world is Eurocentric, but the view that Western cultural
traditions have been instrumental in its creation. The authors discussed
above share a suspicion of cultural explanations, but the "uniform growth"
and "recurrent growth" theories offer quite different justifications for
it. The "uniform growth" scholars, all under postcolonialist influence,
often give no particular reason for their materialist bias. They simply
assume materialism to be "scientific." If they offer a reason, it will
usually be the Marxist principle-which exercises a lingering influence
on the minds of many who are not real Marxists-that matters essential to
survival must always take priority. The argument is deceptively obvious.
The necessities of life must override all other considerations, but the
necessities of life do not operate all the time. The anthropologist C.
R. Hallpike argued that, for primitive cultures, "It is extremely difficult
to be maladaptive, because almost everything will work," and so they run
most of the time on the principle of "survival of the mediocre." Complex
cultures, on the other hand, are subject to more competition, but they
also have many more devices to immunize themselves from contamination by
foreign values and to manipulate "rational choices."
The
nineteenth-century distinction between base and superstructure has always
depended more upon ideology than evidence. It seems certain that material
factors, demographic and economic, lie behind great worldwide changes of
prehistory, like the spread of agriculture and the rise of the state, but
these are hardly "history" in the usual sense. In ordinary history, where
time is measured in centuries or decades rather than millennia, it seems
more useful to adopt Eric Jones's concept of cultural forces as brakes
and filters. If the filters are fine enough to block economic change, which
Jones has acknowledged can happen "over periods which are quite long in
policy terms," then all changes must happen simultaneously, and there is
no reason to call one more basic than another. Ample room remains for disagreement
about the relative importance of cultural factors-for example, I tend to
place more importance than Jones on the power of cultural variables to
reinforce or retard economic development. But this is not the place to
pursue that argument. I wish to offer a more modest proposal: Until compelling
evidence can be presented, any research strategy that asks us to begin
by putting on blinders to vast areas of human experience should be politely
declined.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Douglas Campbell's, "Speaking of Books: Your Loyal and Loving Son"
Dennis
Showalter wants readers to know in his commentary for Your Loyal and
Loving Son: The Letters of Tank Gunner Karl Fuchs, 1937-41 that Horst
Richardson's translation of his father's personal letters offers the story
of a man, not an historical model. The letters cover Fuchs' life from service
in Nazi Germany's Labor Front to death in action as a tank commander during
the 1941 Moscow offensive. His missives reveal a romantic idealist, musical
artist, and devoted family man who also dedicated himself to Adolf Hitler
and to Nazi Germany's wartime success.
Richardson
wants to demonstrate that his father, a Nazi enthusiast, was also a decent
man. Reviewing and then discarding historical arguments about group or
national culpability for Nazism, Showalter asserts that Fuchs' letters
exemplify how people's individual motives often determined Nazism's attraction.
Textual annotations highlight Fuchs' parochial, chauvinist worldview, but
they also insist that Fuchs was not a monster, opportunist, or group automaton.
Fuchs griped as much as any soldier, but like many Germans he had faith
in the Nazi state. Nazism was a friendly local presence that also appealed
to the romantic's desire for national regeneration. For those examining
why average Germans followed Hitler, Fuchs' diary provides one impression
of Hitler's regime at its zenith-and not a post-defeat expiation.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Jacob Kipp's, "Speaking of Books: Soviet Naval Doctrine and Policy,
1956-1986"
In
1968 the United States Naval Institute Press published retired Navy Commander
Robert Waring Herrick's revised dissertation, Soviet Naval Strategy,
which, like the works of John Erickson and Raymond Garthoff, broke new
ground in the exploitation of open-source materials, especially Morskoi
sbornik and Voennaia mysl', in the study of Soviet military and security
policy. In 1988, the year of Admiral Sergei Gorshkov's death, Herrick published
a second volume devoted to the admiral's thirty-year tenure as Commander
in Chief of the Soviet Navy. As Herrick acknowledges in his new book, Soviet
Naval Doctrine and Policy, 1956-1986, his earlier work developed out
of his own experiences-naval intelligence training; a tour as assistant
naval attache in Moscow; and close collaboration with Nick Shadrin, a defector
from the Soviet Navy who wrote his own dissertation on Soviet naval development
and then was lost in late-1975 Cold War intrigues in Vienna. Herrick was
part of a small, dedicated group of professionals who devoted their professional
attention to the study of Sergei Gorshkov's oceanic navy, which included
the Center for Naval Analysis, theSoviet Writings Group, and the Dalhousie
Maritime Workshop, run by Mike MccGwire.
Herrick's
three volumes offer a complete and effective treatment of Soviet naval
doctrine and policy from its beginnings to the end of the Soviet state.
What has yet to added to this discussion is a more detailed and shaded
picture of the personalities, especially of Gorshkov and his chief advisors.
The scholars who undertake that task will find a solid foundation for their
work in Herrick's volumes.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Richard Raack's, "Speaking of Books: Stalin's Other War"
Within
the last five years, at least five books on Stalin's intent to attack Hitler
have been launched into the surging international debate about Stalin's
war plans. Most of the new books-like the earlier milestones in the debate
from Carl O. Nordling, Joachim Hoffmann (in Das Deutsche Reich und der
Zweite Weltkrieg, v. 4, now in English), and Viktor Suvorov-have been
produced by writers without university connections . The new books from
professors tend to exonerate Stalin of plotting a war. Does that tell us
anything?
Weeks's
slender volume, based wholly on printed sources, is a must for scholars
and history buffs who study the Second World War, and especially for those
skeptics who still doubt Stalin's warlike designs. Weeks judiciously weighs
his Russian and English-language sources. He tells his story engrossingly.
He also provides in appendices key documents that have previously not appeared
in English, or which have been hard to find, including Stalin's speech
to the Politburo of August 19, 1939. In this long-neglected text
the Soviet boss tells why he made the Pact with Hitler, and how he intended
to exploit it. Weeks also summarizes some current Russian textbooks on
the controversial topic-an outstanding and insightful contribution to understanding
Russia's current refusal to face its past.
"Weeks's
few errors and his lack of attention to the vast German-language bibliography
do not prejudice his main conclusions. Stalin's Other War offers
a compelling and insightful assessment of Stalin's plans for an invasion
of Nazi Germany.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
MARK
NOLL'S AMERICA'S GOD: A SYMPOSIUM
From
Margaret Bendroth's, "Wheaton Jeremiad"
For
Noll, ideas have immense consequences. He is clearly and unapologetically
writing intellectual history, albeit carefully contextualized with other
narratives of economic, political, and social change. Though Noll recognizes
the importance of economic factors and regularly acknowledges the contributions
of African-American and female preachers, he gives formal theological ideas
primacy of place. He contends that Protestant theology fundamentally shaped
early national culture and proved far more elemental in molding American
thought and culture than, for example, the emergence of market capitalism.
Thus his analysis offers a deep appreciation of religion's importance and
a thoroughgoing critique of its role in American society. In America's
God religion receives primary credit for sharpening public awareness
of the moral evil of slavery, but it also emerges as fundamentally compromised
by its central role in the ultimately secular task of nation-building.
Noll's angle of vision often obscures the actions of people on the margins.
Unlike much recent work in American religion, Noll's story is written "from
the top down," focusing on the overarching structures of American society,
not its diverse particularities. Within his framework, his analysis is
both cogent and intellectually satisfying; indeed, given the book's extraordinary
scholarly depth, any complaint about scope is apt to sound like empty carping
at a job well done.
Still,
the relative absence of women is worth notice, not least because the religious
discourse Noll analyzes would have played to a mostly female audience.
Scholars of American religion rarely attempt to account for the persistent
two-thirds majority of women in the pews, much less assume that women's
dominance had any direct effect on the historical trajectory of churches
or denominations. The lack of attention to women in America's God is,
in my view, surprising. The problematic role of women as a majority constituency
in American Protestant churches routinely banned from public leadership
should constitute more than a nuance to any argument about democratization.
Even today, many Christian bodies prohibit women from voting in denominational
assemblies or from ordination to church leadership, simply because they
are female. The issue is not simply a matter of "equal time" for female
protagonists, but the explanatory scope of Noll's argument about religion
and the development of democracy in America: Does it apply to the majority
of church members?
I
think it does. Most historians will recognize that Noll's book covers a
period of time in which religion was becoming thoroughly entrenched in
the female sphere and increasingly tangential to the world of middle-class
men. Scholarly analyses of this "feminization" have, on the whole, tended
to disparage either women or religion: on the one hand, "feminization"
brought about the sentimental horde of women who reduced divine sovereignty
to a socially impotent form of Victorian Christianity; on the other, American
religion became mired in consumer capitalism incapable of attracting red-blooded
men busy in the marketplace. But I think Noll's theological angle on early
nineteenth-century culture offers a more generous accounting for Protestantism's
gradual drift toward women and away from men. His argument allows us to
wonder, for example, whether the contingent post-Edwardsian God simply
made the most sense in the domestic sphere. Studies of religious movements
dominated by women show a consistent emphasis on suffering and loss, reflecting
women's primary role in childbirth and parenting-and suggesting that, for
many women, God tends to be immanent rather than transcendent. Alternatively,
the fundamentally cooperative God of the nineteenth century did not perhaps
relate as easily to a masculine world that denied contingency and demanded
instead self-mastery and individual achievement. Though blanket generalizations,
of course, are always wrong or at least intellectually risky, perhaps the
larger point is clear: Noll's Protestant divines planted the seeds of a
particular religious demise, not necessarily a universal one.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Laurie Maffly-Kipp's, "A Calvinist Country?"
The
devil in America's God is not in the details, which are marvelously
rendered. Rather, the bedeviling feature of the book is Noll's nuanced
but nonetheless insistent assertion of recurrent themes within American
historiography that are, at the very least, worth more analysis. In at
least three ways, Noll's story is familiar. He emphasizes the exceptionalism
and isolation-if not the altogether positive distinctiveness-of
the American intellectual scene; he narrates an intellectual declension
from a unified Puritan "canopy" to a less rationally vigorous theological
nationalism that eventually topples under its own thin foundations; and
he portrays the buildup to the hermeneutical rupture of the Civil War almost
exclusively as an argument between northern and southern white Protestants
over slavery and the Bible.
Thorough
examination of these themes would take several more books, but they can
be outlined. Noll argues that the colonial Calvinist theology of the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries, which resembled European theologies in many respects,
began to disintegrate under the strain of the importation of Enlightenment
political images and language into religious discourse. Morality became
"virtue," and the meaning of "freedom" was liberalized and extended to
equate political values with the liberties of the soul before God. Jonathan
Edwards thus represented both the last great Puritan theologian and the
first thinker to "narrow" his vision of the community of the elect to make
it consonant with secular understandings. In the decades after the Revolution,
the tremendous growth of evangelical adherence and the enormous energy
put into organizing the new nation-mounted principally by evangelical denominations,
hence the comparison to the U.S. postal service-drew intellectual energies
inward as well. American theology became exceptional as it turned its focus
away from Europe and towards its own development.
Noll's
version of events is all true and makes for a marvelously rich account.
But he also paints a geographically isolated picture of the North American
religious scene. Strikingly absent are the many ways in which antebellum
Americans were simultaneously extending their own reach overseas, across
borders, and westward into new territories. The international missions
movement, whose birth is commonly attributed to the Andover theology, was
fueled by-and, in turn, reshaped-new turns in theology during the early
nineteenth century. The movement proved one of the most potent organizing
tools in the evangelical arsenal. Although United States imperial reach
did not achieve its greatest height until after the Civil War, the early
years saw intense activity to extend national borders through a war against
Mexico, which generated considerable theological reflection among Protestant
clergy. Even organizational efforts often seen as "domestic" causes, such
as abolition and tract distribution, engaged Americans in a broad network
of international evangelical support. Yes, Methodists in the United States
spent considerable time organizing the new nation, but they frequently
relied for help, both practical and ideological, upon international contacts.
Noll's narrative to the contrary, it is difficult to separate the elements
of evangelical development that focused Americans inward on the nation
from those that brought them into contact with Christians and non-Christians
in other parts of the world.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Ann Taves's, "America's Distinctive God"
While
Noll's primary concern is with the Americanization of evangelical theology
rather than United States history, he makes a strong case that "religion,
especially as embodied in a full spectrum of evangelical churches," played
a more decisive role in creating a national culture than historians have
traditionally recognized (194). The contribution was both ideological and
organizational, and Noll gives particular credit to the burgeoning "Methodist
web of classes, circuits, quarterly meetings, conferences, and annual conferences"
(196). Noll uses a recent study of the role of the postal service-the nation's
largest federal agency-in nation building to provide perspective on the
evangelical contribution. By 1850, the Methodists alone "had constructed
almost as many churches as there were post offices and employed almost
as many ministers as there were postal workers." Taken as a whole, he estimates,
"the evangelical churches employed nearly double the personnel, maintained
nearly twice as many facilities, and raised at least three times the money
as the Post Office" (201).
Noll's
argument leaves historians with much to ponder. For those specializing
in religious history, the differences between evangelical denominations
are instructive. Although Methodists played an important role in knitting
the nation together organizationally, Congregationalists and Presbyterians
elites provided the intellectual leadership. Nor was denominational growth
linked to the embrace of an Americanized theology. Methodism grew most
rapidly during the Revolutionary Era, when it was still largely untouched
by Americanization. As Noll acknowledges, "the Methodist experience shows
that it was entirely possible for a traditional Christian message that
had not been adjusted to the norms of American ideology to flourish
in the new American nation" (340). He further suggests that Methodist theology
was "most creative" in the early years, when it was least philosophical
and least Americanized. As Methodism became more middle class, the majority-apart
from the holiness movement-embraced the common intellectual discourse forged
by Congregationalists and Presbyterians and lost much of its distinctiveness.
The
case of Methodism, coupled with Noll's depiction of what it meant to Americanize
theologically, raises questions about the ways in which other denominations
were or were not Americanized. A fair amount of attention has been devoted
to the Americanization of denominations such as Catholics, Lutherans, Jews,
and Latter-day Saints. Noll's detailed analysis of the Americanization
of Congregationalist, Presbyterian, and later Methodist theology provides
a foundation for revisiting the question of Americanization, this time
with a greater emphasis on the role of theology. To what extent did the
Americanization of theology-as opposed to,say, the adoption of the English
language or practices that mimicked Protestants-shape perceptions of what
was American in the realm of religion? To what extent could traditions
that did not abandon all sources of authority but "the [Christian] Bible
alone" ever Americanize? Did what it meant to Americanize theologically
change significantly in the post-bellum period? If so, how?
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Mark Noll's Response
It
is still my opinion that, comparatively speaking, Lincoln's "Meditation
on the Divine Will" from September 1862 was, as I averred in the book,
one of the most remarkable theological comments of the period: "In the
present civil war it is quite possible that God's purpose is something
different from the purpose of either party." Precisely the tragedy of Christian
theology in this period was that it took someone who never joined a Christian
church to make this statement. By contrast, the Christian theologians (though
to differing degrees) pretty well knew what God was up to. Precisely the
tragedy of Lincoln (from my angle as a Christian believer drawn to theologians
like Augustine, Luther, Calvin, Pascal, Kierkegaard, Barth, von Balthasar
who have preserved God's mysterious sovereignty as an essential part of
their Christian faith) was as I stated it in the book, that for Lincoln
and a few other non-believers like Emily Dickinson, "to be faithful to
the God they found in their own hearts-or in the Bible, or in the sweep
of events-they had to hold themselves aloof from the organized Christianity
of the United States and from its preaching about the message of Jesus
Christ." It is not my view that Lincoln gave utterance to adequately Christian
theology; it is my view that, compared to the Christian theologians of
his day, his vision of God came much closer to what an adequate Christian
view should be than did theirs.
In
these terms, the question of whether Lincoln realized "the true American
mission" lies beyond the scope of my book. While confessing that I do revere
Lincoln, as Fox-Genovese notes, I also confess that, to the extent possible
for a modern academic, I have as close to no opinion about the nature and
destiny of the United States as it is possible to have. America's God is
first about theology, not the United States.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Robert Herzstein's, "Judgment and Restitution: Goldhagen, the Catholic
Church, and Anti-Semitism"
Goldhagen
has depicted German culture as Jew-hating and devoid of pity, but he then
expects free will on the part of its offspring to defy it-thus ignoring
his own evidence regarding the power of anti-Semitism and, worse, overlooking
the impact of ten years of relentless and ubiquitous anti-Jewish propaganda.
The killers were Jew-hating brutes, sometimes lurking under cultivated
exteriors. Goldhagen's expectation that the perpetrators should have overcome
the culture that he, more than any other author, has foisted upon them,
may be a pious wish, but it is bad history. That a few Germans acted better,
or a few bishops helped Jews, hardly vitiates the major point. I can judge
the killers and condemn them to death based on my values, and I do not
believe it matters much to concede that Eichmann bragged about choosing
freely, since his values and ambitions drove him to act as he did. Like
a lot of Germans, he thought he was free, and within his own murderous
culture he was. But free will cannot coexist with a culture of un-freedom,
and the only way to defeat its remorseless, programmed progeny was to crush
them and the culture that bred them. In a culture cleansed of state-sanctioned
hatred, people could truly make free choices-and most Germans since 1946
have chosen well.
Goldhagen's
portrait of the popes and their actions or inactions during the Holocaust
presents similar challenges. Pius XII did not care all that much about
the Jews, but he worried a lot about his Church and the safety of the Vatican.
He, too, acted "freely" in conformity with prejudice and cultural blinders.
True, he was supposed to be a man of great moral stature speaking for and
to millions of devout Catholics. But when confronted with Nazi evil, he
flinched, negotiated, equivocated-acting more like a lawyer and a diplomat
than a moral leader. Goldhagen holds Pius XII to the highest standard of
free will after depicting him and his clerical forebears as anti-Semites
to the core. Goldhagen describes the anti-Semitic culture that produced
Pius XII, then seems surprised and hurt that Pius XII did not act to defend
the Jews, choosing instead to act after 1940 as a chief operating officer
protecting the interests of the Church. Pius XII did not even necessarily
protect the interests of Catholics, for sometimes he placed good relations
with the Germans above the interests of persecuted Catholic Poles. Once
again, free will in Goldhagen's narrative is the deus ex machina
that failed. Goldhagen expects Pius XII to shed anti-Semitic attitudes
and beliefs and to intercede on behalf of the Jews. After all, the Eighth
Commandment and the Catholic Catechism both forebade bearing false
witness, and in Goldhagen's view, Pius XII was supposed to apply the Catechism
to
anti-Semitism and overlook the synoptic gospels-which Catholics revered.
Goldhagen's high moral standards speak well for him, but they respond to
history, rather than evoke it. Until 1965, most popes and Catholics did
not see the accusation of Christ-killing against the Jews as libel, so
why should they have discarded the old view of the Jews in 1935?
The
fluke election, well after 1935, of a brash pope, combined with growing
unease about his predecessor's silence, combined to change history. Only
a revolutionary new pope, John XXIII, a rescuer named Angelo Roncalli during
the Holocaust and a great humanitarian unencumbered by past hatreds, could
break the mold. His pontificate does suggest a German analogy in one sense:
John was to the Church's view of the Jews what the defeat of 1945 was to
German culture-a rare cataclysmic event that changed everything. Pius XII
most assuredly did not feel free; John XIII began the process of liberation,
tragically late.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Vincent Lapomarda's, "Reckoning with Daniel J. Goldhagen's Views on the
Roman Catholic Church, the Holocaust, and Pope Pius XII"
Goldhagen
makes much of the example of the Danish Lutheran Church, which, he argues,
shows that the Catholic Church could have helped the Jews by speaking out
against the Holocaust (p. 51-55). The example of the Lutheran Church in
Denmark only proves how Goldhagen fails to recognize that people and circumstances
differ. Even if one were to concede that Goldhagen and his sources are
correct in their view of Pius XII's alleged silence, Peter Steinfels, in
his column in The New York Times (May 24, 2003), offered a more
likely comparison when he recalled how vocal Pope John Paul II had been
against the war in Iraq: "Those who imagine that the Holocaust could have
actually been halted by a clarion call from Pope Pius XII should take note."
Although
the words and actions of the Church under Pius XII could not stop the Holocaust,
the objective evidence shows that the papacy was not as silent in word
and deed as Goldhagen alleges. When, for example, Pius XII spoke out in
his Christmas Message of 1942 to defend the victims of the war, The
New York Times characterized this intervention as "a lonely voice crying
out in the silence of a continent," and the Nazis interpreted it as an
attack on Germany and a defense of the Jews. The testimony of German Foreign
Minister Joachim von Ribbentrop at Nuremberg confirmed that the Nazis had
received "a whole deskful [sic] of protests from the Vatican" during
the war. To this testimony can be added the fury of the Reich's Propaganda
Minister Josef Goebbels at the protests broadcast on Vatican Radio. Overwhelming
praise from Jewish sources for Pius XII, as recorded in the appendix of
Hans Jansen's latest book, Pius XII (2003), suggests that the Church
did more than any other international agency, person, or state to help
the Jews during World War II.
Godhagen's
pursuit of moral judgment justifies, for him, the culpability of the Catholic
Church under Pius XII. On the one hand, the Church supported and committed
political transgressions, crimes, criminal incitement, and acts of anti-Semitism,
thereby incurring moral and political blame. Its interventions on behalf
of the Jews were, at best, ambiguous. On the other hand, the Church was
guilty of sins of omission before, during, and after the Holocaust. The
Church under Pius XII was also forsaking the souls of Catholics. For Goldhagen,
who has accepted John Cornwell's interpretation in Hitler's Pope
(1999), Pius XII was not only an anti-Semite, a blind anti-Communist, a
servant of Adolf Hitler, and an appeaser in the pursuit of peace, but he
was afraid to risk his life for the Church-he failed to issue a public
condemnation of the persecution of the Jews, even when he knew about the
Holocaust; he was negligent in remaining silent or in making no public
display of his protests against the Holocaust; he was wrong to fail to
excommunicate the Nazi leader; and he helped the Jews less than any other
world leader. What Goldhagen lacks is a true appreciation of the Church's
traumatic struggle for survival against the Nazis, who were determined
to eradicate Christianity itself. In those circumstances, the Church under
the Pope was quite limited in its ability to defend Catholics, not to mention
Jews, against the Nazi reign of terror. Goldhagen's analysis offers no
sense of the complexity of the decisions Pius faced when, as one of latter's
contemporaries observed, with respect to Communist Russia and Nazi Germany,
the choice for the Pope was between the cholera and the plague.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
From
Barbara Finlay's, "Was Tertullian a Misogynist? A Reconsideration"
Perhaps
no church father has received as much condemnation for his attitudes toward
women as Tertullian (Quintus Septimus Florens Tertullianus, c. 155-c. 225).
From Simone de Beauvior's The Second Sex, which claimed that Tertullian
associated woman with the body, temptation and evil; to Elizabeth Schussler-Fiorenza,
who accuses him of having a "deep misogynist contempt and fear of women,"
many scholars and students have made similar charges. Marie Turcan, in
a 1990 article in Vita Latina, claims that "The woman is in [Tertullian's]
eyes a public menace" and describes his attitude in his essay on women's
dress (De cultu feminarum) as follows: "The man has everything to
fear from her, and the first Adam would have done well to be wary about
her. The eye with which he looks at her is singularly critical, and not
only in De cultu. No occasion is lost to show her vain, conceited,
sensual, frivolous, avid and at the same time stupid and cunning."
Such
claims have been picked up by a wide variety of non-specialists and widely
repeated. A current sociology textbook on sex and gender, citing a brief
comment and quotation by Rosemary Radford Ruether, asserts that"Tertullian,
a Church Father of the second century, laid the blame for the fall of humankind
entirely on the shoulders of Eve and all of her daughters. It was woman
and woman alone who was to blame for sin and evil." The textbook then lays
the blame for later misogyny at Tertullian's feet: "Tertullian felt no
compunction in preaching his antifemale beliefs, thus setting the stage
for others to follow in one long litany of misogynous sentiment." In short,
the cliché that Tertullian was uniquely and wholly misogynist has
become widespread.
The
majority of writers illustrate their charges against Tertullian primarily,
if not solely, by reference to one infamous passage from one essay (De
cultu)-a passage often taken out of context and as the sole exemplar
of Tertullian's attitude toward women. In it he accuses women of being
"the devil's gateway." Even so, a few recent scholars have questioned the
widespread attributions of misogynism to Tertullian, usually pointing to
other essays that do not support the impression given by the "devil's gateway"
passage. While De cultu does appear to blame women for the origin of sin
and for encouraging men's sin through appealing to their sexual desire,
it is not wholly representative of Tertullian's expressed and lived attitudes
towards women. The corpus of his writings includes comments and sections
relevant to his views of women scattered among different treatises, many
of which are overlooked by critics. A broad survey of his comments about
and to women and their roles and experiences in the church indicates a
more complex thinker than is often assumed. The current clichéd
assertions about Tertullian's misogyny are based on a superficial reading
of his works, and a closer reading raises questions about the validity
of the accusations. Specifically, we need to explore the various nuances
of Tertullian's attitudes toward women and their role in the church, as
expressed in his surviving written work.
Back
to top of page
Join
The Historical Society and subscribe to The Journal of The Historical
Society
INTRODUCTION
by
Elizabeth Fox-Genovese
As
a rule, the goal of revolutions is, in John Higginson's words, "to make
short work of traditions." Typically, they seek to wipe the slate clean,
frequently with violence and in blood. Those who approve them, follow the
sensibility of Jean Paul Sartre in Les Mains Sales (Dirty Hands),
his play about the consequences and benefits of collaboration with the
Communists in the 1940s. The roughest fights will dirty your hands, no
matter how pure your goals. Arguably, history even suggests that the purer
the goals, the dirtier the hands that effect them. Or, in a more familiar
version: You can't make an omelet without breaking eggs. Those who balk
at these necessities reprove the shedding of blood and the trampling of
lives in any cause, no matter how worthy. The ends do not justify the means,
and the power required to realize the ends is more than likely to prove
both oppressive and corrupting. The road to freedom is too often strewn
with corpses, and, to borrow again from Higginson, "the dead cannot collect
what is owed them."
Yet
even a clear-sighted recognition of the dangers does not entitle us to
settle for a unilateral view of the matter. War and revolution have been
the midwives of countless changes that most of us regard as beneficial.
It is hard to contest the benefits of abolishing American independence
or the abolition of slavery. Occasionally great changes, like the fall
of the Soviet Union, come with an astounding absence of violence-but even
when effected peacefully, they may leave everyday life fraught with persisting
violence, struggle, and lack of basic necessities. If nothing else, we
should recognize the early years of post-Soviet Russia as a preview of
what is occurring in Iraq. The end of an evil regime-whether through violent
overthrow in war or revolution or through quiet collapse-will not necessarily,
or even probably, give way to the emergence of a peaceable kingdom.
Any
attempt to grasp the nature of major historical change, must begin with
an understanding that the past-however battered-does not just lie down
and die. Revolutions aspire to erase tradition for the excellent reason
that the more astute revolutionary leaders recognize it as their most dangerous
foe. To take one brief but telling example, neither the French nor the
Russian revolutions ultimately succeeded in their attempts to abolish or
radically transform marriage. Sexual freedom, including the easy availability
of divorce, enjoyed a brief sway, but eventually succumbed to the people's
attachment to the organic units that provided their best defense against
the intrusions of state power and, however ironically, the state's need
for the regular reproduction of population and its early socialization.
Our
efforts to understand and interpret historical change, whether violent
or peaceful or the more familiar combination of struggle and compromise,
only complicate the problems, especially when the changes are provoked
by natural phenomena like drought or flooding. This issue opens with Elias
Mandala's reflections upon the crisis in African food studies-a different
problem, let it be noted, than the recurring crises in African food supplies.
Mandala does not minimize Africans' wrenching problems in assuring adequate
supplies of food for their people, but here he primarily focuses on the
ways in which Western scholars portray those problems. In the 1970s and
1980s, the Ethiopian and Sahelian famines spurred a flurry of scholarly
interest, but thereafter interest rapidly declined and has now virtually
disappeared. Meanwhile the problems of basic provisioning persist. But
even when scholarly discussions of African food problems flourished, they
missed a fundamental problem.
Scholars
have primarily viewed African food supplies from two main perspectives,
the environmentalist or the whiggish or liberal. Both, but especially the
second, follow the logic of what Mandala calls "time's arrow"-a linear
model that focuses upon the consequences of the transition from precapitalist
to capitalist social relations of production. This "whig" or liberal model
has the great advantage of revealing the ways in which the advent of capitalism,
not infrequently through the efforts of foreigners, effectively destroys
traditional agricultural practices and relations, not least by revolutionizing
property relations among African peasants. But the premises and methods
of this work, to which Mandala initially subscribed, failed to account
for much of what was occurring. On the verge of abandoning his project,
he turned to a radically different set of sources: the peasant women of
Malawi. From them he learned of the preeminent importance of time's cycle
in their lives. If famine was the dramatic product of time's arrow, recurring
dearth was the product of time's cycle.
Both
the linear and the cyclical models figure in any convincing historical
account, although few historians regularly combine them. In the case of
Malawi, the rural and the academic perspectives on the availability and
communal distribution of food rarely meet, with the result that academics
simply do not see the ubiquity of recurring periods of hunger among peasant
populations. As Mandala argues, it is misguided to assume that the extraordinary-in
this case, famine-necessarily illuminates the ordinary-the routine of the
everyday, which is punctuated with bouts of dearth. Where famine can kill,
dearth can stunt children's physical and mental growth. Dearth can also
strain community relations and even introduce tensions into the communal
meal. Yet if we can ill afford to ignore the cyclical quality of everyday
life, it is no less dangerous to ignore time's arrow, which illuminates
changes that are affecting the ways in which people throughout the globe
experience and attempt to cope with the ordinary, everyday aspects of their
lives.
John
Higginson's discussion of state terror and collective violence in South
Africa during the brief period following the lifting of the state of emergency
in 1990-91 also highlights the potentially disastrous consequences of linear
change for rural people. In this instance, the goal was to "wipe out" the
potential rural constituency for recently "unbanned" parties, thus controlling
the outcome of the first "free" election. As Higginson insists, "Violence
and aggression in any society automatically embrace related problems of
social and political costs, morality, social cohesion, and authority to
pose a critical question: Who, through the agency of the state, can do
violence to whom?" During South Africa's revolutionary transition, the
rural population suffered a disproportionate share of violence, which ultimately
resulted in an increase-not the usual decrease-in the rural population
from 44 percent of the total in 1993 to more than 51 percent in 1997. With
this increase of more than seven percent in less than five years, has come
a dramatic increase in the percentage of economically vulnerable black
people who live in rural areas-a percentage that has risen faster than
the increase in rural black people over all.
Higginson
suggests that historians might learn much about the events of the past
decade-or century-in the Transvaal from the great French historian Georges
Lefebvre's Les Paysans du Nord, but the lesson would be a negative
one. For what centuries of peasant protest, culminating in the full-scale
revolt of the French Revolution, accomplished in France, died stillborn
in South Africa. Rather than gain access to land, the peasants of the Transvaal
were herded into compounds, assigned to an arbitrarily created fictive
state, and consigned to a life of partial, piecemeal employment and grinding
poverty. Although the current South African government describes them as
"fully employed," their condition eerily resembles the condition of cyclical
hunger that weakens the peasants of Malawi. In both cases, tradition has
been trampled under the feet of large indigenous and foreign economic interests,
and the rural groups that cling to its shreds have been rendered powerless
to introduce it into national politics or policies.
In
the 1960s, the anthropologist Clifford Geertz, studying Indonesia, advanced
the notion of involution to capture the effect of the expanding global
market upon peasant economies in third world societies. Similarly, Ester
Boserup, an economist, studying Africa, analyzed the way in which the British
introduction of private property in land effective stripped rural women
of any claim upon the land and its fruits. Since their pioneering contributions,
scholars in various fields have called attention to the many ways in which
rural populations-especially women and children-can be immiserated by so-called
development. Agricultural regions, as both Mandala and Higginson demonstrate,
do not remain in a steady state while change swirls around them: most of
them become poorer, while a few became capitalist enterprises that produced
for a global market. They are also likely to retain, in Mandala's words,
a strong allegiance to cyclical as opposed to linear time.
The
claims of tradition challenge historians no less than these historical
actors. Barbara Finlay's essay on the purported misogyny of Tertullian,
a second century Christian Church Fathers, which together with Mandala's
frames this issue, challenges us to look at these questions from another-and
unaccustomed-angle. Tertullian is known as a man of learning and intellectual
influence, which has increased his vulnerability to feminist charges of
misogyny. Too polite to say that the charges derive from inadequate familiarity
with Tertullian's work or respect for the context within which he wrote,
Finlay carefully demonstrates that most of his accusers rely on a single
passage in which he accuses women of being "the devil's gateway." She acknowledges
that his De Cultu in which the passage occurs "does appear to blame
women for the origin of sin and for encouraging men's sin through appealing
to their sexual desire," but she cautions that before rushing to judgment
we should consider the broader context of his work, especially his adherence
to the Montanist heresy.
Finlay
dispels a host of misunderstandings in her discussion of second-century
Christian teachings, especially Tertullian's, on the origins of sin, the
relations between the sexes, the proper place of sex in human life, the
role of women in the early church and among the Montanists, and, above
all, on the strong sense of mutuality between women and men. Her discussion
reintroduces a semblance of balance and historical perspective into our
assessments of men's attitudes towards women during the first centuries
of Christianity. Contemporary presentism has made it exceptionally difficult
to recognize the possibility that the meaning of and standards for respect
for women may have varied historically and differed radically from our
own modern expectation, much less that women may have been more likely
to see themselves as members of groups than as individuals in the modern
sense of the word. Today in many circles, resentment of religions that
ascribe different roles to women and men runs so high that it virtually
negates the ability to understand women's experience and aspirations in
societies and historical epochs other than our own.
Finlay
makes a signal contribution to clarifying Tertullian's thought and discrediting
the most extreme feminist outrage. She notes that Tertullian saw as different
from men and held them, conjointly with men, responsible for original sin.
She also, although doubtless inadvertently, adds another dimension to our
understanding of Mandala's Malawi peasant households. Tellingly, it was
a woman who instructed Mandala in the dynamics of dearth and introduced
him to the economics and rituals of food distribution within the community.
Mrs. Zachepa introduced Mandala to njala, recurrent or seasonal
hunger, and, in doing so revealed much about the social dynamics of her
rural community. Strange as it may seem, that community probably shares
many features with the communities of the second-century Mediterranean
amid which Tertullian lived. And notwithstanding the vast difference in
intellectual sophistication, both kinds of communities belong to the world
of rural households that has dominated most of human history. In such worlds,
women may be denigrated, even abused, but they are seen as essential to
the spiritual life of the group; are recognized as necessary to the survival
of the family and beyond it the community; receive respect for their specific
functions; are required to observe the sexual standards of the community-and
often cruelly punished if they do not.
Few,
if any, traditional societies did not foster some combination of misogyny
and idealization of women. Immune to the homogenizing principles of modern
individualism, must societies have taken the difference between women and
men as foundational and, in the measure that men have disproportionately
controlled culture, represented women as "the other." From any other perspective
than that of the modern Western world, Tertullian's treatment of women
would be remarkable not for its misogyny but for its respect for women's
dignity as women and the interdependence of women and men. Ironically,
the individualist principles that so sharply color modern and postmodern
views of the world are distinctly Western in origin and owe a special debt
to Christianity, with its insistence on the equality of all souls in the
eyes God.
If
the strands that converged into modern individualism derived from many
sources, the French Revolution of 1789 proved central to their political
consolidation. The great Latin American historian, Frank Tannenbaum, enjoyed
telling his students-teasing the left-wingers among them-that the Russian
and Chinese Revolutions they considered important were but mere footnotes
to the French Revolution: "It upset a perfectly good and stable society,
and we have not stopped paying for it yet." Lecturing in the 1950s, Tannenbaum
could take for granted a general understanding of revolution as the violent
change in political regime presumably provoked by a measure of unrest in
prevailing social and economic relations. Disagreements about causes and
the desirability of the results abounded, and opinions varied from the
French men and women who pulled the curtains as a sign of mourning on Bastille
Day to Maoists, and everyone in between. Few would admit to disapproving
the results of the American Revolution, but even those who saw it as an
unequivocal good differed about its causes and the implications of its
results. On one point only did something like consensus prevail: The revolutions
had occurred and had brought significant change in their wake.
Today,
as Hugh Ragsdale argues, it would be rash to expect even that modest level
of agreement. Focusing primarily on the Russian Revolution, Ragsdale explores
the dramatic changes in scholars' assessments of the causes, nature, and
results of the English, French, and Russian Revolutions. Around the middle
of the twentieth century, in his account, the historiography of both the
English and French Revolutions was heavily influenced by materialist interpretations,
frequently with a socialist or explicitly Marxist cast. Differences notwithstanding,
the leading historians all embraced a whiggish-even teleological-perspective,
which links them to Mandala's category of time's arrow. They all viewed
these revolutions as monumental steps in the progress toward increased
political freedom, respect for the rights of the individual, the separation
of church and state, and the recognition of absolute private property.
To Marxists, who viewed the revolutions as bourgeois, they were at least
necessary steps toward the ultimate goal of socialism.
The
main attacks on this dominant narrative initially came from historians
who questioned the progressive social content of the revolutionaries' goals
and, especially, the revolutions' beneficial social results. Alfred Cobban
suggested that the French Revolution may have retarded rather than promoted
the advent of capitalism in France. Those who followed Cobban's lead moved
toward the position that the Revolution had not been social at all, but
political. Their conclusions opened the way to what has become known as
the "linguistic turn," which, according to Ragsdale, effectively reduces
the Revolution to the "private sexual problems of the royal family" or
other cultural microcosms. Ragsdale applauds the contributions of a groups
of historical sociologists who have restored structure and causation to
the discussion, but in the end he suggests that the scholarship of recent
decades has left us with little more than a gragbag.
Historians
of the Russian Revolution have faced a different order of problems, for
which the recent work on the English and French Revolutions has offered
little help. The collapse of the Soviet Union has influenced the ways in
which historians perceive its revolutionary origins, with different consequences
for those of different political persuasions. The many left-wing historians
who were drawn to the study of the Russian Revolution now face difficult
questions about Marxism and socialism as both theory and politics. Sheila
Fitzpatrick, a leading historian of revolutionary Russia, earns Ragsdale's
admiration for her ability to rethink fundamental issues. Her recent work,
Everyday
Stalinism, on everyday life in the Soviet Union exemplifies the general
tendency of the field, namely to reverse the pattern for the English and
French Revolutions by moving from political to social history. But notwithstanding
the existence of such fine discrete studies, the field seems to lack direction.
The situation is not one in which time's circle has replaced time's arrow:
one would be hard pressed to find a historian of any of these revolutions
who viewed it as part of a cyclical pattern endemic to human affairs. If
cycle there is, it lies in recurring historiographical fashions. As Ragsdale
writes, "The pursuit of fashion or the flight from convention in a discipline
whose charge is the preservation of tradition threatens now and then to
drive historical writing ever farther from what the common reader can recognize
as history."
In
a discussion of the significance of birth dates, David Krein proposes a
new pattern of classification, which, in turn, suggests new aspects of
causation. Krein has studied the British House of Commons from 1841-1859,
meticulously tabulating a series of decisive votes. If nothing else, his
work demonstrates the unique value of quantification in forcing us to look
beyond received opinion and our own expectations. Historians have made
it easy to assume that party affiliation, which may be taken as a rough
indicator of political leanings or philosophy, provides a good preliminary
guide to voting blocks in the Commons. Krein demonstrates that it may not.
Analysis of specific votes reveals that the most important bond among members
may be that of generation, which often led members to cross party lines
in important votes. Ragsdale also notes that at least one study of the
English Revolution found generation to offer the best explanation for the
behavior of individuals. And it is hard to doubt the significance of young
people's living through the same experiences at the same age. Problems
nonetheless remain, beginning with the plasticity of generational boundaries.
But generations do have the charm of joining time's arrow-they succeed
one another-to time's circle-they are always with us. And Krein helps us
to see what historians can gain by considering their impact.
The
articles in this issue illustrate the vast reach of big historical questions.
Sooner or later, every historian confronts the competing claims of linear
and cyclical theories of history, even if only indirectly-or even unwillingly.
Is this person or situation or event something new under the sun or simply
a new version of a familiar story? Even agreement upon these difficult
questions does not ipso facto determine how we tell the story, and
how different historians tell the story-what they choose to emphasize,
what they choose to ignore, and how they choose to present it-is a recurring
theme in this issue. Our times have sharply, and sometimes noisily, called
the writing of history into question. This epidemic of self-conscious agonizing
has led some to doubt the possibility of writing history at all: "how do
I position myself in relation to the other, the past, the multiplicity
of subjectivities"? Or, in a shameless paraphrase, "Do I dare to write
a line"?
Beneath
the flurry of postmodern questions about the nature of facts and the position
of the historian, an older generation of questions sometimes seems to get
buried, notably the longstanding debate between idealists and materialists.
Writing of the "Assault on Eurocentric History," Doyne Dawson returns them
to center stage, but in what I at least find a disconcerting new guise.
Dawson argues that the struggle between the so-called Eurocentrists and
their opponents pits idealists against materialists. As he presents the
case, the attack on Eurocentric history is being waged as an attack on
the noxious idea that culture-superstructure as it used to be known-accounts
for the gap in development between Europe and the rest of the world. Apparently,
the argument is that only some form of geographical and ecological determinism
can explain that gap in an equitable and non-racist manner. What those
who have cast themselves as champions of the non-Western world cannot countenance
is any suggestion the cultural superiority in any way explains Western
development.
Dawson
opens a plethora of questions. It would seem that those who deny the significance
of culture are also, in some way, trying to defend equality among the races-and
presumably among their cultures as well. At issue is the refusal to credit
any special status to, for example, Western scientific thought. As Dawson
allows, beyond a certain point a rigid distinction between idealist and
materialist factors makes little sense. As he says, the world is Eurocentric
in the measure that Western technological and economic power has set the
standard for everyone else. He also insists that this outcome was not foreordained
and that "if the push into modernization had not happened in Europe, it
would probably have been made somewhere else sooner or later, most likely
in Japan, followed by Korea and China. Perhaps. But Japan is something
of a loaded choice since it is the only non-Western society to have passed
through a recognized period of feudalism. In the end, Dawson follows Eric
Jones in viewing culture as providing the brakes and filters for material
factors. This position offers one version of the sensible view that materialist
and idealist factors interact in ways so complex as to preclude any unilateral
determinism. The entire debate nonetheless offers a delicious example of
prevailing intellectual confusions, for it reveals the postmodern enemies
of Eurocentrism as hard-core materialists, who deny any decisive role to
culture-a position that is difficult to reconcile with their insistence
upon the plasticity of "reality," which is constructed by the observer.
In
Speaking of Books, short reviews by Douglas Campbell, Jacop Kipp, and Richard
Raack turn to different aspects of military history, all of which intersect
with the themes in this issue. How do we evaluate the German tank gunner,
Karl Fuchs, who emerges from his letters as a "decent man," who "had faith
in the Nazi State"? Jacob Kipp and Richard Raack take us from the personal
experience of war to the intentions and strategies of those who plan and
wage it. Kipp raises questions about aspects of a three-volume work on
Soviet naval doctrine and practice, notably its lack of attention to individual
personalities and motives. Raack strongly endorses a "slender volume" that,
in his view, fully confirms Stalin's intent, as early as 1939-1941, to
wage war against Hitler. The reviews' focus on Germany and Russia during
World War II reminds us that those wounds have yet to heal and that many,
as Raack suggests about the Russians, still find it difficult to face their
past.
The
Holocaust enjoys a special place among the World War II wounds that remain
open, and Daniel Goldhagen continues to probe them. In this issue, we pick
up the debate over his work with an exchange between Robert Herzstein and
Vincent Lapomarda over Goldhagen's new book, A Moral Reckoning: The
Role of the Catholic Church in the Holocaust and Its Unfinished Duty of
Repair. For Goldhagen, who, according to both of our authors, has done
little if any primary research on his topic, the Catholic Church bears
major responsibility for the Holocaust, which the Vatican failed to denounce
or oppose. Herzstein does his best to give Goldhagen the benefit of the
doubt, but even he seems to find many of Goldhagen's charges improbably.
Lapomarda, who knows the Catholic sources better than Goldhagen, displays
less even patience. In the end, it almost seems that the differences between
Herzstein and Lapomarda are more differences of degree than of substance-at
least with respect to Goldhagen.
The
more serious and potentially divisive questions concern the nature of the
Holocaust, responsibility for it, and appropriate responses today. Goldhagen,
who had initially laid the blame on ordinary Germans now lays it squarely
on the Catholic Church. In the case of ordinary Germans, it was difficult
to prescribe a fully satisfactory response. An entire change of heart and
mind, together with an admission of culpability, would seem the obvious
response, but they are notoriously difficult to monitor and enforce. In
the case of the Catholic Church, Goldhagen devises a much neater solution:
The Church must reform its very structure, doctrines, and sacred texts
in such a way as to eradicate all traces of anti-Semitism from its past
and all possibilities for its recurrence in the future. In other words,
the Church must cease to be the Church and transform itself into something
like a democratic and decentralized Protestant denomination. And to ensure
the a genuine transformation of hearts and minds, it must rewrite the entire
New Testament, especially the Gospel of St. Matthew, removing all negative
references to the Jews, especially any part they may have played in the
death of Christ.
Proposals
to reform Christianity have been with us since the first century, and many
have favored some form of liberalization or democratization. The great
challenge for the most radical, namely the Reformation, lay in preserving
the essentials of denominational unity and discipline. Our continuing debate
over Mark Noll's America's God has touched upon some of the main
issues as they played themselves out in America. In this issue, we conclude
the formal symposium-although not discussions of the topic-with contributions
from Margaret Bendroth, Laurie Maffly-Kipp, and Ann Taves, followed by
Mark Noll's response to the entire symposium. The contributors to the symposium
all warmly praise Noll's impressive work, which they clearly expect to
stand as the cornerstone of American religious history for the foreseeable
future. Each also has criticisms, and their criticisms generally fall into
a common pattern. Bendroff points to Noll's tendency to view the story
of American Protestantism after Jonathan Edwards as one of loss-a falling
off from a vision that could encompass both intellectual and religious
passion. She, like Maffly-Kipp and Taves, also calls attention to Noll's
tendency to restrict the active cast of characters, mainly at the expense
of women and African-Americans.
All
of the contributors note Noll's primary focus on Calvinism, mainly at the
expense of Methodists, and Taves suggests that he slights the importance
of the missionary impulse. Bendroff credits him with offering "a more generous
accounting for Protestantism's gradual drift toward women and away from
men," which included a growing preference for an immanent rather than a
transcendent God. And she concludes by noting "the almost eerie relevance
of his narrative to the events of the past year, in which God's will has
been regularly invoked on behalf of military and political ends." Similarly
Laffly-Kipp concludes with the evocation of African-American biblical hermeneutics
and a protest against Noll's inclination to encase American religion in
a "Calvinist box," while Taves ends with the question of religion's role
in supporting the sense of American exceptionalism in the world. All, in
other words, gently challenge Noll on the significance of the past for
the present and, perhaps unintentionally, raise the question of whether
present standards may appropriately be applied to the past.
America's
God belongs firmly in the orbit of time's arrow, notwithstanding Noll's
sense of what we have lost. In this respect his admirable intertwining
of the religious and secular stories invites the queries of his commentators
about contemporary implications. And his response to the commentators could
hardly be more gracious and appreciative, even as he holds firmly to the
ground he has carved out. In this perspective, I was more than a little
surprised that he devoted considerable attention to one of my sentences
from the introduction to the previous issue. I had queried his apparent
claim that Abraham Lincoln, an unbeliever, embodied the ultimate significance
of American religion. Here, he responds, "It is not my view that Lincoln
gave utterance to adequately Christian theology; it is my view that, compared
to the Christian theologians of his day, his vision of God came much closer
to what an adequate Christian view should be than did theirs." And, in
these words, he effectively gives away the ground he thought he was reclaiming-and
confirms my main point. By the Civil War, American Protestantism had undergone
a hefty infusion of secular concerns. The problem was not that people had
abandoned the faith of their fathers but that they were demanding that
it conform to their lives in the world.
In
more ways than one, Abraham Lincoln embodied that revolutionary impulse
which "makes short work of tradition." His defense of a glorious cause
depended upon breaking with the past rather than realizing its promise.
The ensuing omelet may well have been worth the broken eggs, but we gain
little by banishing them from story. The gains and losses of previous revolutions,
like the tragedies that engulf contemporary Africa, may have much to teach
us about assessing the respective claims of time's arrow and time's circle
in the history of the modern Western world.