t_h_s t_h_s t_h_s
t_h_s
ths ths

 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
-

-
t
t
 
Joseph S. Lucas and Donald A. Yerxa, Editors
 


Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

 


Peter N. Stearns, "WESTERN CIV AND WORLD HISTORY:CONFLICTS AND COMPLEMENTS"

Lauren Benton, "How to Write the History of the World" 

Michael Cook , "Islam: History's First Shot at a Global Culture?" 

Counterfactual History: A Forum

David Schaberg, "Truth and Ritual Judgment: On Narrative Sense in China's Earliest Historiography" 

Sanjay Subrahmanyam, "Europe and the People without Historiography; or, Reflections on a Self-Inflicted Wound" 

Jorn Rusen, "Morality and Cognition in Historical Thought: A Western Perspective 

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

WESTERN CIV AND WORLD HISTORY:CONFLICTS AND COMPLEMENTS
by Peter N. Stearns

Anyone conversant with the history teaching scene in the United States over the past twenty years knows about the running battle between Western civ and world history as foci for survey courses served up to college freshmen and not a few high school students. The conflict has several fronts. Coverage competition looms large. It is impossible to do justice to the standard topics of a Western civ course and the ambitious canons of a world history course in the same year. A common effort at compromise, the high school world history course (usually 10th grade) that is in fact 67% Western, is legitimately ridiculed by world historians as providing a civilizationally skewed vision of what the world was and is all about. 

Competition over values is at least as fierce, and ultimately more intractable. While some partisans of Western civilization courses are primarily attracted by the comforts of routine and familiarity, others, including a number of political and educational leaders, see in the course a defense of superior traditions in an uncertain world, an opportunity to preach unified values to an increasingly diverse American student population. Thus the 99-1 United States Senate vote against the world history portion of the “history standards” issued in 1992, which insisted that any educational recipients of federal money should have a “decent respect for the values of Western civilization.” Thus second lady Lynne Cheney’s assertion that 9/11—a tragedy that seemed to many a call for greater understanding of the world at large—showed how essential it was to rally a round Western values and a Western curriculum. World history partisans, in some instances, have replied in kind with a gleeful effort at West-bashing and (as critics rightly pointed out in the history standards debate) a virtuous attempt to shield other civilizations from adverse comment. 

This aspect of the conflict reflects the resurgence of cultural conservatism in the United States, but it also picks up on the history of the Western civ course itself. The course was designed in the early decades of the 20th century by American educators eager to demonstrate the deeper roots of their own upstart society—in another period of rapid immigration—but also concern e d about diplomatic instability following World War I. As one partisan put it, the Western civ course was designed to help students make a choice between “utopia and barbarism.” In this vein, innovators conceived of Western civ as, effectively, the only civilizational tradition, with a straight line from ancient Egypt and Mesopotamia to the glories of Anglo-American constitutionalism. They saw their course as a mixture of triumphant coverage and an inculcation of precious, but now threatened, values. World historians, by no means uniform West-bashers, simply have to dissent from this tradition. Their vision must encompass a number of different civilizations (or larger world forces that downplay civilizations altogether), and their values, implicitly emphasizing cosmopolitanism and tolerance, point in an alternate direction as well. 

In practice, to be sure, the battle has not raged as bitterly as periodic rhetoric might imply. In the Advanced Placement arena, both world history and European history programs are flourishing (the former is gaining ground, in part because its recent emergence leaves more room for growth). Colleges and universities differ in their choices for survey courses, and some programs, as at Stanford, have combined a traditional Western requirement with imaginative comparative offerings. The idea of sequences of courses, as a logical solution to the dilemma of choice, has not penetrated very far, because the American educational system is so resolutely chaotic where history is concerned and because partisans are unwilling to yield terrain at any particular point. It would be possible, for example, to see high schools as offering a civilizational approach, followed by college-level world history, or vice versa, but that assumes a level of coordination that simply does not exist in the United States, as well as a willingness of, say, world historians to abandon high school in favor of college (or Western civists to cede college), which so far has proved to be too much to ask. But pure Western civ is on the decline— most state requirements insist on some world coverage, though often in Western-oriented amalgams that displease world history purists—and a continued evolution toward a greater awareness of global history is likely. 

Yet one crucial aspect of the tension between world history and Western civ has not been adequately explored, if only because Western civ advocates fear any concession while world historians are often too busy figuring out how to downplay or readjust the West to give serious thought to more imaginative amalgams. Consider the following solution. The West should be viewed as one civilization among several, rather than the whole show. At the same time, the West should be granted analytical significance that goes beyond either debunking or rueful acknowledgements of modern power. Now a series of interesting opportunities arises, which permit efforts to interpret the Western tradition within a legitimate world history framework. 

The key is comparison, a standard world history tool that now needs to be deployed in the Western civ arena as well. What, in fact, are the major distinctive features in Western institutions and values as the civilization has unfolded across many centuries? The question is oddly unasked; particularly in Western civ courses themselves but also in many world history surveys. Partly it goes unasked because we have become accustomed to a factual narrative, a set of historical stories, that pass for conveying what Western civilization is all about (the same turgidness can creep into the coverage of other civilizations in world history, but it is less prominent if only because the civilizational traditions are less deeply established in our teaching conventions). And if, in the more specific Western civ tradition, we assume that “Western” is both distinctive and better by definition, the need for explicit comparison is simply bypassed. Putting the same point another way: the Western civ teaching tradition has always been implicitly comparative—the Western story is older and better—but rarely explicitly so. Analytical linkage between Western civ and world history depends on bringing latent assumptions out for focused examination. 

Comparison, in turn, yields a number of ensuing questions. When, first of all, did Western civilization begin? The Western civ tradition assumes the answer is coincident with the emergence of civilization itself, but in fact this is hard to sustain when Western civilization is handled with the same inquiry about origins that would apply to Indian, Chinese, or Middle Eastern civilizations. Western civ courses, as they have turned into more standard survey narratives, have often shortened the timespan involved, beginning with Greece and Rome, or the Middle Ages, or even later. But they, too, have usually ducked explicit inquiry into when the West actually begins, because dealing with these issues assumes a capacity to define a distinctive Westernness. Talking directly with students about the classical versus medieval options (both can be defended, depending on what aspects of the Western tradition seem crucial) is an initial way of putting Western civilization in a framework compatible with the treatment of other civilizations, and therefore with world history. 

After origins, one moves to key changes in the Western tradition, to the principal periodization of Western history evaluated in comparative context. William McNeill once argued that the West has changed more than other major civilizations. I’m not sure this is a defendable proposition (here, too, explicit comparison would be revealing). But certainly in the early modern period the claim applies, and this raises the issue of what remains Western even amid rapid change, and also how the definition of a distinctive Westernness evolves as well. In dealing with change, a focus not only on familiar topics, like the parliamentary tradition, but also on other key areas where Westernness may apply, like gender relations, will greatly improve the analysis. 

By the early modern period as well, the question of where Western civ was and is gets added to issues of effective origins and major change. Like many civilizations, the West has had a shifting geography, and it has generated borderlands or zones of unusual contact where issues of inclusion or differentiation simply cannot be avoided. (Similar issues apply to East Asian civilization—is it a whole, or must it be divided among China, Japan, Korea, and so on?) For the West, connections to Eastern and Central Europe (being redefined in the contemporary world once again) and even to Russia, and also to the Americas and Australia/New Zealand require explicit analysis that in turn will enhance the capacity to discuss what the essentials of the Western tradition “really” are. That the same discussion requires teachers and students to confront some “exceptionalist” claims, particularly for the United States, adds to the challenge but also, ultimately, to the potential for integration. 

From the late 19th century onward, questions two and three (capturing change within the Western tradition and dealing with shifting geography) are further refined by the need to deal with the considerable Westernization of other parts of the world—Japan being a leading case in point. As other societies successfully incorporate industrialization, consumer culture, and parliamentary democracy, does a definably distinctive West remain? Here again is a compelling focus both for the later stages of a Western civ course, taught in a world history context, and for dealing with one major case of a larger question about homogenization and differentiation in closing out a world history survey. 

Comparison is the most obvious way to move from assumptions in the Western civ tradition to the kind of discussion that is compatible with world history, but there are other bridges as well. Along with comparison, intersocietal contact is a key technique in world history. Elements of the Western civ tradition have, of course, long stressed contact— the kind that emanated from the West from the early modern period onward. A world history approach must incorporate Western generated contacts, but it adds two points to the analysis. First, it urges a closer look at the West as a recipient of influences from other societies—not a brand new topic, but underexplored in the more triumphal versions of the Western civ tradition. This means, particularly, lots of attention to the West as an imitative society in the post classical (medieval) period — where, in fact, comparisons with other imitators, like Japan or sub-Saharan Africa, are quite revealing. The second addition, here particularly for more modern times, involves the realization that contacts are complex, that what the West sent out from the 16th century onward, from Christianity to consumerism, gets variously interpreted and syncretically combined, a process very much still going forward . 

It goes without saying that a more analytical approach to Western civilization, derived from a world history context, embraces both thorns and roses. Some relatively distinctive features of the Western tradition will seem positive (particularly since we inevitably evaluate under some influence from this same tradition), but others, like a willingness to enslave or the modern Western penchant for racism, are more troubling. Comparison can serve neither triumphalism nor West-bashing entirely. 

The analytical issues evoked in this sketch a re complex and designed for debate. They do not resolve agonizing practical issues of competing coverage. But comparative analysis can cut through some of the often sterile debate between the two survey options. Certainly, students in a Western civ course that looks to other societies for measurements of Western distinctiveness, and is open to the importance and complexity of contacts, will have an easier time moving into a world history program, should some sequencing be possible. A Western-oriented world history course, though still potentially misleading, becomes less objectionable if analytically sharpened. Above all, a willingness to deal seriously with the Western tradition—but with more explicit analytical tools—improves the possibility of incorporating Western history into a world history program. Even coverage decisions are improved through a willingness to focus on comparative essentials. To be sure, the compromise is slanted to the world history side, though it builds on assumptions that need to be tested within the Western civ tradition itself. But the capacity to find the West in world history (along, of course, with other major traditions; that’s the whole basis for comparison) should facilitate more constructive conversation between two still hostile camps. 

Peter N. Stearns is provost and professor of history at George Mason University. He has taught and published widely in both Western civilization and world history and currently chairs the Advanced Placement World History Committee. His most recent book is Western Civilization in World History (2003), the latest installment in Routledge’s Themes in World History series, which he edits.

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
 
 

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

HOW TO WRITE THE HISTORY OF THE WORLD Lauren Benton

In one of Jorge Luis Borges’s short stories a royal mapmaker is asked to fashion increasingly accurate maps of the kingdom until, finally, he covers the kingdom with a map. This parable is a warning to all historians but especially to world historians, who may struggle more than others with pressures simply to “cover” time and territory. Reaching beyond mere coverage is crucial to the field’s development, and to its status within the profession. How can we write the history of the world in a way that is not just broad but also broadly influential? 

This question poses itself at a time when world history has already arrived as a serious research enterprise. Once the nearly exclusive realm of a few—William McNeill, Philip Curtin, Alfred Crosby, and some others—the field now draws scholars who no longer consider an association with world history as a mark of hubris, a paean to mass marketing, or evidence (God forbid) of a preoccupation with undergraduate teaching. The field has its own journal, the Journal of World History, which has seen the quality of its articles rise steadily and now routinely publishes both original research, much of it done by junior scholars, and important synthetic pieces. Meanwhile, scholarly interest in the topic of globalization has helped to forge an interdisciplinary audience with an interest in the longue, longue durée

Yet questions remain about the sorts of methodologies aspiring world historians might embrace and promote. Aiming for comprehensiveness and relying on older narrative techniques are not serious options. Without a conceptual framework, the data threaten to overwhelm argument. Otherwise, we could sensibly choose to produce a 5,000- book series, each title evoking John E. Wills’s recent book 1688: A World History; that is, we could write the history of the world one year at a time. 

Whatever else its virtues, world history has not produced a significant volume of methodologically thoughtful discussions or theoretically influential studies. There are, to be sure, discernible methodological patterns and debates in the literature of world history, and some of these do contain lessons for other subfields. Following the title of Donald Wright’s well-crafted book from 1997, The World and a Very Small Place in Africa, one approach involves alternating attention between global processes and local experiences. This methodology informs a number of prominent world history initiatives, including efforts to place formerly insular national histories in global perspective. But the approach may ultimately prove less important to world historical writing, and to fields seeking a connection to world history, than two other common strategies. 

One of these approaches we might label circulationist. Its objects of study are the movements around the globe of—in no particular order—commodities, capital, ideas, people, germs, and ways of marking ethnic and religious difference. Like so many tops spinning, these circuits together comprise what C.A. Bayly has called “archaic globalization” in the early modern period and what observers of the contemporary scene call simply “globalization” (forgetting, sometimes, that it has a history). By shifting our gaze from one sphere of circulation to another, we simulate a perception of the whole of global interconnectedness. Following Arjun Appadurai, we can give these circuits names— either his unwieldy labels of ethnoscape, bioscape, financescape, and so on, or the more traditional Latinate categories we already associate with established areas of study, such as migration, diffusion, or expansion. 

Another approach to globalization in its early and late forms is less familiar but just as important. Rooted in comparisons, it purports to uncover the structural similarities of polities that may be distant in place and time. Here the historian finds globalizing influences by surmise, and by arithmetic; so many similarities in so many places suggest common connections to forces crossing borders and oceans. When done well, this technique reveals hidden continuities. It focuses our eyes not on global circulation but on its imprint, origins, and contexts: for example, status and class distinctions, strategies of resistance, institutions of rule, and nationalism. 

Circulationist projects appear to be in much greater supply. In part, this is because of a certain transparency of social theoretical constructs related to the movement of people, commodities, and ideas. For example, the concept of “networks” has worked its way into mainstream historical studies and has provided a vocabulary for historical writing on topics as diverse as European migration, Third World urbanization, and the transnational diffusion of ideas. In part, the proliferation of circulationist studies reflects the institutionalization of regional historical studies and their logical development. For example, the acceptance of Atlantic history as a bona fide area of research provides legitimacy —and professional cover—for scholars wishing to map Atlantic circuits and follow them wherever they might lead, even if this means overstepping the boundaries of an already expanded Atlantic world. 

Yet it is also true that many circulationist projects remain relatively undeveloped. Thirty years after Pierre Chaunu mapped, in Braudelian fashion, the movement of shipping from and to Seville, we still do not know enough about regional or global circuits of people and goods (let alone microbes). As Alan Karras’s study of New World Scottish “sojourning,” Karen Barkey’s work on Ottoman qadis, Alison Games’s research on cosmopolitan English colonists, and other complex migration stories remind us, patterns and understandings of long-distance movements are much more varied than historians of a generation ago believed. Many of these circuits are still in need of documentation, including the movement of both official and non-official personnel within and across empires. As for commodities, scholarly interest in consumption has played an important role in widening and deepening the analysis of global trade. But here again, one has the clear impression that we are at the edge of a vast and varied area of study, with much more to explore and explain besides commodification, symbolic capital, and circuits of silver. 

As developed and promising as circulationist world history may be, structural approaches to world historical analysis are newer still—and, in combination with studies of movement, perhaps potentially more revealing. This is somewhat paradoxical because comparative world history has some of its roots in a familiar, old-fashioned comparative approach. As David Armitage has pointed out in surveying trends within Atlantic history, an older comparative history juxtaposed different civilizational areas and sought explanations for their diverging trajectories. This kind of comparison is still with us, as we have been reminded by new attention in the work of Bernard Lewis and others to the old question of where the Islamic world has “gone wrong.” We also find it in the continuing debate about the timing of European versus Asian economic development that has seized the attention of the so-called California school of economic historians. 

There is another strand of comparative history, though, with roots that are better established in historical sociology than in sociological history. This approach analyzes multiple cases involving broadly similar historical processes in order to advance generalizations about “big history.” In sociology, we think of Charles Tilly, Jeffrey Paige, and Theda Skocpol as prominent comparativists in this vein; in history, exemplary works include Michael Adas’s early book on millenarian movements, Philip Curtin’s study of trade diasporas in world history, or Patricia Seed’s flawed but interesting comparison of European ceremonies of possession. Rather than comparing trajectories and tallying up the factors “needed” for historical change of a certain kind, such comparative studies examine the structural logic of conflicts or processes in particular places. Global patterns are seen as emerging out of the repetition and replication of similar social tensions and practices, while these are in turn understood as influenced by familiar global circulationist currents. The methodology has the advantages of privileging the kind of careful case analysis that historians claim as their strength and of placing social conflicts and discourse, broadly defined, at the heart of the problem of defining international order. 

I began with this approach in conducting research for my book Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400- 1900 (Cambridge University Press, 2002). The noticeable dearth of historical studies treating law as a global phenomenon has no doubt had something to do with the imperfect fit between traditional legal history and circulationist models. Departing from both, the book analyzes the ways in which law constituted an element of global ordering before the emergence of international law and the interstate order. In early modern empires, including European overseas empires, and in other sorts of polities, too, legal orders were characterized first and foremost by jurisdictional complexity. Religious minorities, communities of traders, and subject populations were expected to exercise limited legal authority over their own community members. The claims of states did not include a monopoly over law, and membership in a legal community was only sometimes defined territorially. This dynamic of multicentric law was both rooted in particular places and so widespread as to constitute an element of international ordering. To give just one example, Portuguese agents arriving in West Africa in the 15th century were aided in setting up trading posts by the homology that existed between their understanding of their limited jurisdiction over Christian subjects and Africans’ acceptance of the legal authority of diasporic traders over their own community affairs. 

Jurisdictional complexity produced both discernible institutional patterns and also, sometimes, transformative conflicts. Legal pluralism established rules that were there to be broken or changed, and legal actors at all levels of the colonial order proved to be adept at maneuvering through and, in the process, altering the legal order. One of the interesting conclusions of colonial legal histories is that pressure for the creation of colonial states came sometimes from indigenous actors rather than from the metropole, which in many cases labored to limit its own jurisdictional claims and minimize administrative costs. Over the course of the long 19th century, institutional configurations shifted— gradually and sometimes only partially—in the direction of state claims to legal supremacy. In this way, the emergence of a global interstate order was the product of politics in particular places, rather than the result of metropolitan or Western designs, or of some incontrovertible systemic logic. 

This example shows that comparative analysis need not propose a model or experience (of capitalist development, state formation, or modernity) to be used as a benchmark for the study of divergent trajectories. It is also important to note that global circuits— of labor, capital, and ideas—are not irrelevant to patterned social conflicts but also do not necessarily hold the key to their understanding. In some ways, this sort of comparative approach builds on the same strengths that make historians so good at placing local histories in global context. Attention to the local is indispensable to the ability to generalize about the global. Yet the technique of juxtaposing broad trends with the history of any “very small place” cannot by itself confirm broad insights about global shifts and their origins. 

Comparisons of this type, it turns out, may be surprisingly compatible with a p p roaches influenced by postmodern perspectives. Both post colonial histories and a recent strain of scholarship in British imperial history have analyzed iterative structures within various arenas of discourse on imperialism. Here the echoing effect of structural similarities occurs not across a range of cases but within different facets of a global enterprise. As Nicholas Thomas told us nearly a decade ago, a version of world history can be rendered vertically, as the study of “projects ” stretching from centers of rule to imperial borderlands. 

Both horizontal and vertical variations of comparative world history present theoretical and practical challenges. Comparing structures across many cases may suggest functionalism if one is not careful to emphasize the contingency of outcomes in all cases. And asserting the essential similarities of various unconnected arenas of discourse may border on the banal, as when David Cannadine in Ornamentalism promotes “hierarchy ” as an organizing trope of British imperialism. While a combination of care and flair may provide an escape from these shortcomings, there is also no question that we are describing merely a comparative perspective, not a theoretical answer to the problems of writing global history. At the same time, we can affirm that world history may be written with the express purpose of producing theoretical insights and methodological innovations. Coverage is dead; long live theory. 

Regarding practical challenges, the central problem may become one of sheer effort. Mastering the complexities of conflicts or discourse in a range of places or cultural milieux requires a great deal of time, expertise, and travel to collections, not to mention mastery of multiple languages. Yet these obstacles may appear less formidable as multi-sited research becomes more accepted by funding agencies and as the boundaries of regional subdisciplines continue to be eroded by the circulationists. 

Despite these and other obstacles, there are compelling intellectual reasons for making comparative history at least as common as circulationist projects in world history. The approach lends itself to the study of a wide range of social, cultural, and political conflicts and their local-global interconnections. This translates into an opportunity to expand world historical inquiry from its more established base in economic history and its more recent, sometimes disturbingly seductive move toward biological-environmental narratives. Institutions should also be objects of study for world historians—not just transnational institutions, which operated fitfully if at all in most historical periods, but global institutional regimes that have emerged out of common cultural practices and patterned political conflicts. And for those who think institutions are a bore no matter how they are discussed, there are plenty of other topics that do not always lend themselves to fruitful study through a circulationist approach. Aesthetic practices and sensibilities, for example, may be widespread without having come to be so through processes of diffusion. 

I anticipate—and hope—that the better established methods of world history - writing will stay with us. We need more well crafted studies analyzing specific local-global interconnections and also more research into the circulation of people, commodities, ideas, discourse, and, yes, microbes. I also hope that these efforts will be joined by the multiplication of studies that build on the best kinds of comparative analysis, moving beyond questions about different developmental trajectories and probing unlikely elements of global order and disorder. 

Unlike Borges’s mapmaker, we will not have to cover the world with a map in order to understand it. Nor will we be limited to other mapping exercises, such as projecting small scale studies onto a global plane. Instead of cartography, the relevant scientific analogy might turn out to be contemporary astrophysics. Its preoccupation with multiple, unseen dimensions in universes we can only imagine offers the combination of precise analysis and broad conjecture to which world historians might now aspire. And then there’s the lure, however remote, of a grand, unified theory—nothing less than a theoretically compelling history of the world. 

Lauren Benton is professor of history at New York University. Her Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900 (Cambridge University Press, 2002) has received the World History Association’s 2003 Book Prize as well as the Law and Society Association’s 2003 James Willard Hurst Prize for the best book in legal history. 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking


Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

ISLAM: HISTORY’S FIRST SHOT AT A GLOBAL CULTURE? Michael Cook

Collecting coins is a bad habit, but recently I decided to acquire a few Islamic ones. Unfortunately it’s a little late in the day to be entering this particular market: too many people in the Persian Gulf (and not on the Persian side of it) have the same idea. But I’m not competing for the rarities. While it’s true that I get a mild glow from being the proud owner of an unusual coin, my real satisfaction is the kick I get from putting coins in front of my students. The idea is to take abstract historical points and dramatize them in a concrete way. 

Recently, I came by two silver coins that lend themselves admirably to this purpose. As can be seen from the illustration (p. 9), the most obvious thing about them is how similar they are to each other. Both are covered with Arabic inscriptions, and nothing else— and with one exception, the inscriptions are identical. The exception is a sentence beginning “In the name of God” that says where and when the coin was minted—though the formula is the same for both coins (it appears on the left in the illustration, around the margin). As to date, the difference is only a few years: one coin (shown at the top) dates from the Muslim year 107 (725–26 A.D.), the other (shown at the bottom) from the year 115 (733–34 A.D.). The drama lies in the geography. The first coin was minted in al Andalus, as the Arabs called Spain—most likely in Cordoba, since by the year 107 it was already the provincial capital. The second coin was minted in Balkh, a little to the west of Mazar-i Sharif in what is today northern Afghanistan. In other words, two almost identical coins were struck at mints located the best part of 5,000 miles apart . 

By the standards of current globalization, of course, there is nothing remarkable about people doing the same thing 5,000 miles from each other. Our present global situation is the product of the European maritime expansion that began in the 15th century. Nothing quite like it had ever happened before, unless we ca re to compare it with the initial settlement of the world’s continents by our species. But earlier historical developments had from time to time spread a measure of cultural homogeneity over substantial regions of the Old World. A millennium before Muhammad, Alexander the Great set out on a career of conquest that took him from Macedonia to India. Several centuries after Muhammad, Jenghiz Khan was to initiate the Mongol conquests, which issued in an empire that extended from Eastern Europe to China. 

The process initiated by Muhammad was nevertheless more remarkable than either of these. 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

COUNTERFACTUAL HISTORY:A FORUM

COUNTERFACTUAL HISTORY has become increasingly popular in recent years. Witness the success of the What If?™ series, edited by Robert Cowley. Contributors to these books tend to engage in alternative historical thought experiments such as what might have been the outcome of a Napoleonic victory at Waterloo, a Chinese discovery of the New World in the 15th century, or a Theodore Roosevelt win in the election of 1912. Counterfactual history like this is popular and entertaining, to be sure, but does it contribute to a better understanding of the past? One of the most thoughtful critics of counterfactual history is Cambridge University historian Richard J. Evans. In his 2002 Butterfield Lecture at The Queen’s University in Belfast, he cautioned historians about the dangers of “what if” history. Historically Speaking has secured permission to reprint the abridged version of Evans’s Butterfield Lecture that ran in the December 2002 issue of the BBC History Magazine. We then assembled a distinguished panel to comment on Evans’s assessment of counterfactual history. Professor Evans concludes the forum with a substantive reply. 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

TELLING IT LIKE IT WASN’T 

Richard J. Evans

What if William the Conqueror had lost the battle of Hastings? What if Martin Luther had been burned at the stake in 1521? What if the British had managed to hold on to the American colonies in 1776? What if Napoleon had won the battle of Waterloo? What if Lenin had not died prematurely in 1924 but had lived on for another twenty years? What if Germany had succeeded in conquering Britain in 1940? 

Imagining what might have happened is always fun. A very diverse range of serious and distinguished historians has indulged in this pastime, including G.M. Trevelyan, Conrad Russell, John Vincent, Hugh Trevor- Roper, Geoffrey Parker, Alistair Horne, Theodore Rabb, Andrew Roberts, Robert Katz, William H. McNeill, and many others. In recent years, it has become increasingly fashionable to engage in such speculation, and collections of essays have appeared with titles such as If I Had Been . . . Ten Historical Fantasies, edited by Daniel Snowman in 1979; Virtual History, edited by Niall Ferguson in 1997; and What If?—The World’s Foremost Military Historians Imagine What Might Have Been, edited by Robert Cowley in 1998, and so successful that a second volume appeared under the same editor in 2001 with the title More What If?

Historians have generally thought of such mind games as entertainments rather than serious intellectual endeavors. The subtitle of John Merriman’s collection is Chance and Humour in History, while Robert Cowley opens his latest volume of speculations with the complaint that: “One of the troubles with history as it is studied today is that people take it too seriously.” The earliest such collection, J.C. Squire’s If It Happened Otherwise: Lapses into Imaginary History, treated the whole thing as a kind of whimsical parlor game (as Niall Ferguson has remarked, somewhat disapprovingly). Later collections, notably John Merriman’s, do not seem to have escaped very far from such frivolity. Not All Good Clean Fun Yet it’s not just all good, clean, or in some cases not so clean fun. “History involving great people or pivotal events,” complains Cowley, “is out of fashion. Broad trends, those waves that swell, break, and recede, are everything these days. We are left with the impression that history is inevitable, that what happened could not have happened any other way, and that drama and contingency have no place in the general scheme of human existence.” The “what if” approach, he says, can help restore drama and contingency to the place which they ought rightfully to occupy. Cowley’s complaint is, I think, unjustified: historical biography is as alive and flourishing as ever; microhistory has brought a new dimension of the personal and the particular into historical writing; and broad trends and ideas of historical inevitability are more out of fashion than in. Yet, in my admittedly rather old-fashioned view, there are broad general reasons for the proliferation of “what if” histories in recent years; the appearance of so many books advocating the return of chance and contingency to history is not just a matter of chance and contingency itself. 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4


Is the Dark Light Enough?

Edward Ingram

How one envies Richard J. Evans his certainties, his Manichaean view of the world. For him, what happened is good: it happened. What did not happen is bad; not bad in itself, merely a quicks and wise historians will not tread in. And to be so certain that one knows what happened that one also knows what did not; that one can tell the one from the other. The difficulty facing the rest of us unfortunates in appraising the worth of counterfactuals lies not in working out what did not happen, but what did. . . . 
 
 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking


Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

The New Counterfactualists

Allan Megill 

To make sense of so-called counterfactual history we need to get clear about the theoretical issues that counterfactuality raises. We also need to make some distinctions. I would begin with a distinction between two types of counterfactual history, “restrained” and “exuberant.” “Restrained” counterfactual history involves an explicit canvassing of alternative possibilities that existed in a real past, whereas “exuberant” counterfactual history deals in past historical outcomes that never in fact came to be. . . .

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

When do Counterfactuals Work? 

Robert Cowley 

I would like to begin my remarks with two observations. Richard Evans has written a dismissal of counterfactual history that is at once learned and elegant, reasoned and reasonable. In not a few points, if by no means all, I find myself agreeing with him. But why hide my feelings? I am uneasy being set up as straw man in his essay, and I don’t like being lumped, even by inference, with the New Right of history. The Right has never been my chosen refuge. Counterfactual history is not just the domain of conservatively inclined thinkers, as many of the contributors to this issue of Historically Speaking should testify. . . .

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking


Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Counterfactuals and the Historical Imagination

William H. McNeill

Historians can playfully ask “what if” and historians can be foolish when writing imaginary history, too. But there is a serious intellectual kernel behind the game, for there are events, like the failure of the siege of Jerusalem in 701 B.C.E., that did make a quite extraordinary difference in what followed. And by drawing attention to such occasions and wondering out loud how different the world would be, contingent, surprising, unpredictable aspects of the human past can become obvious to most readers. This seems worthwhile to me, since oversimplified schemes for explaining human affairs abound and we are continually tempted to believe everything was somehow always inevitable. . . . .

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4
 

Alternative History and Memory

Gavriel Rosenfeld

What would the field of alternate history do without its opponents? Since its recent emergence into the Western cultural and intellectual mainstream in the last generation, alternate history has garnered increasing attention in no small part due to the enduring opposition to it among many skeptical historians. By giving rise to controversy and sparking discussions such as the one printed in the pages of this bulletin, the critics of alternate history have ended up further contributing to the field’s prominence. For this reason, it is safe to say that without its opponents, the field of alternate history — to paraphrase Jean Paul Sartre’s flawed observations about anti-Semites’ views of Jews— would have to invent them. . . . 
 
 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Counterfactualism Defended

Jeremy Black 

One of the great pleasures of being a “nuts and bolts” historian is that every so often one’s intellectual betters explain what I’m doing. Molière phrased it better, but it is late. Reading Richard Evans’s characteristically thoughtful and interesting piece, I discover that, on at least one occasion, I’ve been “liberal Whiggish” or “conservative, pessimistic,” if not a “young fogey.” For, I must confess, I have employed counterfactuals in From Louis XIV to Napoleon: The Fate of a Great Power (UCL, 1999), published an essay entitled “A Different West? Counterfactualism and the Rise of Britain to Great Power Status” (Francia 28/2 [2001]: 129–145), frequently lecture in the U.S. on the topic “Could the British Have Won the American War of Independence” (not “should”—more interesting, but outside my competence), and have discussed, on radio and in print, the “what if” the Jacobites had marched on from Derby in December 1745. . . . 

<top>

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Good History Needs Counterfactuals

Richard Ned Lebow

Richard Evans is right on target in his criticism of Niall Ferguson’s simplistic and ideologically transparent use of counterfactuals. Ferguson’s two books do a disservice to counterfactuals, which remain an essential—if inadequately exploited—tool of historical and social scientific research. 

Robert Cowley’s two volumes, by contrast, make no pretense about using counterfactuals to do anything other than to alert readers to just how contingent the past really was. This is a useful exercise because the “hindsight bias”—one of the more robust and most heavily documented cognitive biases— leads us to overvalue the likelihood of events that have already occurred. Historical research reinforces this bias. R.H. Tawney observed that it gives “an appearance of inevitableness” to an existing order by dragging into prominence the forces which have triumphed and thrusting into the background those which were swallowed up. No matter how well documented or convincingly presented, historical studies invariably provoke critiques and contending interpretations. . . . .
 


<top>
 
 

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Response

Richard J. Evans

Counterfactual history is just a tool of historical analysis, as Cowley says, and has to be used with caution. It has to be applied in very specific, carefully delimited contexts if it is applied at all, and we have to be aware of its limitations, which are extremely severe. It’s hard enough finding out what was, let alone reaching any kind of tenable conclusions on what wasn’t. But if counterfactual history didn’t exist, then the world of historical debate would surely be a poorer place. In his concluding contribution, Robert Cowley lets slip the fact that he has edited three volumes of What If? In my ignorance, I thought there were only two. I’m off to buy the third one right away. . . . . .
 


<top>
 
 

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Truth and Ritual Judgment: On Narrative Sense in China's Earliest Historiography

David Schaberg 

For historians of early China, a coincidental agreement between traditional Chinese and modern Western taxonomies of knowledge supported, through most of the 20th century, a rather blinkered view of the oldest source texts. Under late imperial China’s predominant fourfold classification system, these texts had been pegged as Histories or, in some cases, as Classics, and were thereby separated from Literature and Philosophy. Scholars could and did admire their literary characteristics, but the latter were ultimately to be considered superfluous in comparison with the historical truths the texts conveyed. Meanwhile, scientific history as practiced by Western and Western- inspired scholars tended to bracket observations on form and style in source texts, focusing instead on content and the value of these texts for discerning historical facts. The situation is a familiar one: it is the state of affairs that Hayden White addressed in his early books and that he and other scholars have worked to change. For a number of reasons, the older view—that literary analysis of source texts may yield appreciations but will not contribute significantly to a better and more critical understanding of the past—has been especially tenacious in the early China field. The source texts are very good, very detailed, and very subtle as narratives of intellectual and political activity. They present themselves, as if anticipating our needs, as unbiased re portage. And, by explaining the course of human events in what must be recognized as Confucian or proto Confucian terms, they provide a still vital wellspring for the mainstream of elite Chinese culture. Little wonder, then, that most readers have preferred to imagine these texts as largely transparent: as snapshots of speech and action undistorted by the truth- and sense-making habits of storytellers. . . . . . .
 


<top>
 
 

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking


Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Europe and the People Without Historiography; or Reflections on a Self-inflicted Wound

Sanjay Subrahmanyam 

In this essay I want to call into question four widely held assumptions in that ill-defined field of postcolonial studies. I certainly share some preoccupations and even assumptions with those with whom I wish to debate. Like them, I am concerned with the tenacious hold that a linear vision of Western history from ancient Greece to the United States of Clinton and Bush (with obligatory pit stops at Rome, the Carolingians, the Renaissance, the Enlightenment, and the Industrial Revolution) has on school and college curricula. I abhor the insidious assumption that to know Europe is effectively to know the world. Also, I am concerned that a recent wave of imperial nostalgia, together with a market-friendly millenarianism, has given new life to the myth that the European colonial empires of the 19th and 20th centuries were really quite benign structures. We are now told insistently that the British Empire nobly brought modernity to the heathens, and that we should all be grateful for it. Yet, I must also part ways with some of the shibboleths of postcolonial studies, which in fact participate in the very constructs that are ostensibly being criticized. Here are some of them. 

1. The celebration of myth, and the characterization of history and historical consciousness as a negative attribute of modernity, one that is moreover probably responsible for many of the ills that beset contemporary societies the world over. 

2. The central place given to European agency, with the rest of the world being reduced in effect to victimhood. In the view of the world that is propagated by many postcolonial studies scholars, Europe continues to act alone, and the role of the rest of the world is simply to react to European initiatives. Thus, the seemingly interesting project of “provincializing Europe” often turns out in large measure to be an examination of how one or the other part of the world takes on board, reacts to, and refracts ideas and initiatives that have a uniquely European origin. 

3. The eager acceptance of an exotic characterization of the non-West. Here, the desire to have the moral upper hand prompts many scholars—in the wake of radical anti-modernists such as Ashis Nandy—to invent the non-West in the mirror image of Europe. Thus, it is claimed that non-European societies and cultures intrinsically incarnate the opposite of all aspects of European modernity. If Europe is possessive, India must be selfless. If Europe believes in growth, India must believe in stasis. And so on. 

4. The acceptance that the study of the non- West must essentially be restricted to its encounter with the West in the period of colonial conquest and rule. This program emerged very quickly as the implicit conception behind Subaltern Studies, which, while claiming to examine South Asian history and society, in fact touched on the period before 1800 in an infinitesimally small proportion of its essays. It is only in recent times that some questioning of this practice has emerged . . . . . .
 


<top>
 
 

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking


Historically Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society

March 2004


Volume V, Number 4

Morality and Cognition in Historical Thought: A Western Perspective

Jorn Rusen

There is an important debate now about the differences between Western and Eastern historical thought. One are a of difference, it is argued, concerns the role played by morality. According to this view, Eastern historical thought retains a lasting commitment to moral values, whereas the West has given up this commitment in favor of a rational or a scientific mode of historical cognition. One can easily find the topos of Eastern spirituality and Western rationality in this qualification of fundamentally different cultural modes of historical thinking. Retaining a fundamental relationship to values gives Eastern historical thought an essentially human quality, whereas the scientific approach to the past dehumanizes history and alienates it from the orienting forces of culture.

In his recent essay, “Cognitive Historiography and Normative Historiography,” Masayuki Sato presents a convincing typology of historical thinking with respect to the basic differences between Eastern and Western cultural traditions. In the East (which for him is Japan and China) the moral tradition of historical thought is still valid, and history serves as a cultural means for guiding the values of people today. Sato argues that in the East Asian tradition there has never been a transcendent basis for history. Historical facts as such have been the only reliable reality for people looking to orient their lives. In the West, on the other hand, historical thinking was rooted in a transcendent religious dimension, though it has since become secularized. 

In my view, however, Sato’s understanding of Western historical thought is flawed. Even in the West, morality has dominated historical thinking. I cannot deny that a rupture occurred at the very moment when historical studies in the West emerged as a distinct academic discipline, bringing with it new truth claims related to empirical evidence. Nevertheless, despite the methodological emphasis on rationality and related claims of objectivity, morality has remained an effective element in the West’s approach to history. And, therefore, making sense of the human past is much the same in the East as it is in the West. . . . 
 
 


 
 

Join the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking

h
The Historical Society, 656 Beacon Street, Mezzanine, Boston, MA 02215 | Tele: (617) 358-0260, Fax: (617) 358-0250
                                                         © The Historical Society | web design by Randall J. Stephens | v. 10/26/05
t
h
ths