Aristotelian Perspectives on Social Ethics Joanna G. Patsioti
|
I. Abortion Concerning the issue of abortion Aristotle's views are not considered as very clear or consistent throughout. We shall examine the relevant passages from both the biological and psychological treatises in connection with other of his contemporary or not medical findings. In our attempt to establish his main approach, we shall also unfold his views on the more modern notions of personhood as they are examined in his ethical and political works. According to the Hippocratic oath, abortion is forbidden as morally unjustifiable. A physician is not to help a woman abort her fetus by giving her an abortive remedy. Concerning the possible influence of Hippocrates by the Pythagoreans we would accept Edelstein's (1) position, according to which the Pythagoreans saw the fetus as an animate human life unconditionally worthy of preservation from the moment of conception. We learn about the Pythagorean views on marriage and procreation from Iamblichus (BII, 211-212) who indicates that a man should take the best of care for bringing a child into the world considering both the time and the way this should happen. What is more important, however, is to relate their views on procreation to their theory of the immortality of the soul. After death the soul disappears like a dream and dwells in a spiritual heavenly world until it reappears cleansed in a new birth. (2) The soul keeps only the fragmented happy moments of each of its cycles on an earthly life and will conclude its dream in the heavenly world, which is interrupted by its visitations (reincarnations) on earth. Thus, it is evident that for the Pythagoreans and, as result, the Hippocratic tradition, abortion would be morally unacceptable, since it stops this journey of the soul the incorporeal part of the human body towards its ultimate enlightenment, i.e. its relation to the divine. After all, such cases of bloody events like abortions, were seen as possible sources of ritual impurity. It is also noteworthy that such a view on abortion would relate to the conservative approach to abortion according to which the fetus has full moral status which implies that its right to life must be respected with the utmost seriousness and an abortion apart from cases where the life of a woman is endangeredis as morally objectionable as any other murder. (3) Moreover, apart from the Pythagorean influence that might give birth to some religious implications along with the moral ones, we should indicate that in the classical period medicine in Greece was devoid of any superstitions or irrational influences and was emerging as a truly rational science. The Greek physicians began to develop a science which was an amalgam of observation, rational methodology, and intuitive perception. (4) Thus, Hippocrates expressed mainly his school's views in that oath and not just the Pythagorean tradition. Having established the medical theoretical framework by which Aristotle must have been influenced let us now follow exactly what he has to say on the moral issue of abortion. In the Historia Animalium (583b10-20) he says:
What we notice in this passage is that Aristotle makes the distinction between the male
and the female embryo attributing different developmental characteristics to each of them,
andthe distinction between effluxion which is a destruction of the embryo within the first
week of gestation and abortion which occurs up to the fortieth day. As Paul Garrick (5)
maintains, Aristotle followed a theory of epigenesis according to which "the
individual organism develops by structural elaboration of the unstructured zygote rather
than by a simple enlarging of a performed entity". What is further noticed is that
Aristotle was well aware of both the contraceptive and the abortive methods used by women
at that time. In fact, he appears to be very agreeable with any contraceptive methods used
as shown from his discussion in the Politics VII, 1335b20, according to which he
would accept infanticide of deformed children as well as a law that prevents the explosion
of the population. What is more important, however, is the last line of this passage in
his Politics "if children are then conceived in excess of the limit so
fixed, to have miscarriage induced before sense and life have begun in the embryo".
The words What should also be noted is that in the Generation of Animals B3, 736a33-736b16, Aristotle maintains that the embryo is not soulless, thus, not devoid of life and it actually possesses the nutritive soul while as it progresses, it also has the perceptive soul in virtue of which it is an animal. He goes on providing a very essential information that the fetuses which are not yet separate must clearly be classed as possessing the nutritive soul potentially, but not actually until they are drawing in their food like the separate fetuses and are performing the function of this sort of soul (736b9-13). What follows from this is that the embryo possesses all the forms of the soul in potentiality (following the distinction between potentiality and actuality in Aristotle's Physics). In other words, the embryo possesses all three kinds of the soul but not in their actualized state as yet ("for all souls must be possessed potentially before actually", 736b15-16) (7) What is equally important is the basic question he poses as to whether the souls are produced in the body without existing beforehand, or they must pre-exist, or some must but not others (736b17-19). His conclusion is that they cannot all pre-exist:
As for the notion of pneuma, he considers it as the heat that acts as the vital force
and it is related to the In fact, this discussion of the potential existence of all the faculties of the soul
relates to the modern discussion of the potential personhood and the fetus' right to life.
A fetus does not resemble a person in any way but if it is nurtured and allowed to develop
naturally it will very probably become a person. On the other hand, we need not conclude
from this that a potential person has a right to life by virtue of being potential. And
even if a potential person does have some prima facie right to life, such a right could
not possibly outweight the right of a woman to have an abortion, since the rights of an
actual person outweigh those of any potential person. (9)
What would be the Aristotelian answer to that? His response would probably relate to his
theory of the will and the notion of II. Euthanasia The moral issue of euthanasia is examined by Aristotle when he discusses the problem of
suicide, although we must state that he did not pay so much attention to it as his teacher
Plato did. He contributes to this problem through some passages in the Nicomachean
Ethics. In the ninth book he opposes to suicide and says that men who have committed a
number of crimes and are hated for their wickedness, actually flee from life and kill
themselves (Q4, 1166b12-15). In his discussion of justice in the fifth book, he regards
suicide as an act of injustice , since it is the voluntary infliction of bodily harm not
in retaliation and therefore contrary to the law (E6, 1138a6-16). He considers it as an
act of injustice against the state rather than against himself, for he suffers voluntarily
and nobody suffers injustice voluntarily. For Aristotle, it probably sounded not only
unfair, that is against the wishes of the state, of which a citizen is always an integral
part (11), but also unwise, something that the However, it is questionable what Aristotle has in mind in either of the above books. In the ninth book most probably he refers to invirtuous people who are habituated to wrong actions and having developed a distorted moral vision could end up harming themselves as well as other people. It is not so clear though what he refers to in the fifth book. He does not explicitly mention the case of diseased people who suffer from incurable diseases and may undergo painful treatments. Would Aristotle morally justify the act of a moral agent-citizen who suffering from a terminal, degenerate disease begs for a mercy death (an assisted suicide, or physician assisted suicide), or even commits suicide on his own? The answer would be negative and unequivocal. In his discussion of courage in the third book he says:
In other words, a voluntary death is morally unjustifiable under any circumstances even if those include the case of a miserable or not easily to endure life. But why would Aristotle exclude those cases of terminally diseased people that suffer so much pain? This is because such a person would be a coward, an invirtuous agent that is not habituated to good actions and his decision is not a proper moral choice, the result of reasoning and a rational desire. In this case, there is no proairesiV involved but the sovereign of a vice, that of cowardice which gives way to extreme fear. By that Aristotle does not mean that the courageous person
Thus, the decision to kill oneself, or ask a relative or even a physician to assist a
person with that is a moral An interesting question that would arise, however, is to what extent such an approach
to the issue of euthanasia violates the principle of moral autonomy. What about the right
to a more dignified death, if life is not endurable? Isn't this a moral agent's right? On
the basis of what we said earlier, Aristotle would not recognize such a right, for a moral
agent is, on the one hand, a free person to plan his/her own life and make his/her own
moral choices on hard life cases, and on the other, s/he is a citizen, hence an organic
part of whole (12) and it is pure injustice, if not to say
selfishness, to view civil life in such a way. As far as the moral autonomy of a person is
concerned, there seems to be an apparent violation but not a real one. In fact, the
Eudemian definition of free will (or voluntariness) allows an agent to do things in his
power (EE, B9, 1225b2ff) but it makes a distinction between a moral mistake What we have noticed throughout our examination so far, is that the Aristotelian
approach to the above moral issues becomes clearer once we direct our attention to his
ethical doctrine of the development of ethical understanding and his theory of action. The
Aristotelian arete (virtue, excellence) denotes not only the notion of a habituated
good ethos but also an advanced stage of ethical understanding that relates to good
ethical judgement. Or, as Aristotle himself says: "For virtue makes us aim at the
right mark and practical wisdom makes take the right mean (NE, Z7, 1144a7-9).
In other words, Thus, the capacity of a "good judgement" is what would be the Aristotelian response to an ethical manager who wishes to maintain a good personal profile and promote the image of his company. And this capacity comes with experience and proper education and upbringing. It is also what is going to help somebody achieve the proper choice in determinate circumstances. It is what will help an agent balance and weigh conflicting concerns and come to a "fair" conclusion. At the same time, the Aristotelian ethical manager must be a man of integrity and an advocate of truth-telling to the extent that this does not violate the objectives of the corporation he serves. Moreover, s/he should be virtuous in the sense that s/he has acquired certain excellences that enable him/her to manifest his/her thoughts and actions in a way that suits the particular endeavors. There must be an honest dealing, fair play, good knowledge, wit and an experienced moral vision. In conclusion, we have seen that the Aristotelian views on the issues of abortion and euthanasia as well as the case of the ethical manager can be established through the prism of his ethical doctrine in connection with the whole of his theoretical framework. For Aristotle, a moral agent should be endowed with the necessary capacities, the prerequisites for a good life. S/he should be able to reach the right decision on a hard life case that relates to any moral issue. And above all, when such a hard reasoning takes place, the Aristotelian moral agent must consider oneself as an integral part of a whole, a part of a community that develops every day and needs all of its members to be active and co-operative, for it is through such a conception of a commitment that a moral agent can fulfill his/her desirable ends. In other words, s/he must consider the choice and the effect that such a choice would have on both his/her life and the lives of everybody involved. |
Notes (1) Reference to Edelstein's PhD dissertation in 1931. (2) (3) Mappes, Thomas A & Zembaty, Jane S (1997): Social Ethics: Morality and Social Policy, (5th ed.), U.S.A.:McGraw-Hill, p.3. (4) Patsioti, Joanna & Rose, Clifford F (1995): "What did the Greeks mean?", Journal of the History of Neurosciences 4, 67-76 (particular reference to p.75). Cf. Longrigg, James (1963): "Philosophy and Medicine: Some early interactions", Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 67, 147-75. (5) Garrick, Paul (1985): Medical Ethics in Antiquity: philosophical perspectives on abortion and euthanasia, Philosophy and Medicine vol.18, Dordrecht: D.Reidel Publishing Company, pp.115-19. (6) Mappes & Zempaty in note (3) p.5. (7) Balme, David M (1972): Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with passages from II.1-3) (translation with notes), Oxford: Clarendon Aristotle Series (General editor J.L. Ackrill), p.63. (8) Ibid., p.160. (9) Warren Mary A (1997): "On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion" (reprinted in Mappes & Zembaty edition above, 10-18), p.15. (10) Cf. Garrick in note (5), p.119. (11) Miller, Fred D, Jr. (1995): Nature, Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics, Oxford: Clarendon Press, reference to pages 47-56 where the organicistic view of the state is examined further. (12) Ibid., pp.50-3, where the natural priority of the polis is discussed further. (13) Kenny, Anthony (1979): Aristotle's theory of the will, New Haven: Yale University Press, p.59. (14) Solomon, Robert C (1996): "Corporate Roles, Personal Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach to Business Ethics", in Donaldson, Thomas & Werhane, Patricia H (ed.), Ethical issues in Business: a philosophical approach, New Jersey: Prentice Hall Series, pp.45-59 (particular reference to p.53). Bibliography Clark, Stephen RL (1975): Aristotle's Man (speculations upon Aristotelian Anthropology), Oxford: Clarendon Press. Edelstein, Ludwig (1967): Ancient Medicine, Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press. Fye, Bruce W (1978): "Active Euthanasia: An Historical survey of its conceptual origins and introduction to medical thought", Bulletin of the History of Medicine 52, 492-502. Gracia, Diego (1978): "The structure of medical knowledge in Aristotle's philosophy", Sudhoff Archiv 62 (No.1), 1-36. Hartman, Edwin (1977): Aristotelian Investigation: Substance, Body and Soul, U.S.A.:Princeton University Press. Jaeger, Werner (1957): "Aristotle's use of medicine as a model of Method in his Ethics", Journal of the History of Science 77, 54-61. Kudlien, Fridolf (1970): "Medical Ethics and Popular Ethics in Greece and Rome", Clio Medica 5, 91-121. Veach, Robert M (1978): "Codes of Medical Ethics: Ethical Analysis", Encyclopaedia of Bioethics 4, 172-9. Westermack, Edward A (1906-8): The origins and development of the Moral Ideas, 2 vols., London: MacMillan & Co. |