Berakhot
19b
The Bavli’s Paradigm of Confrontational Discourse
Menachem Fisch
Rational Rabbis sets forth from the observation that a close
reading of a variety of authentic and alledged tannaitic texts reveals a major,
deep-reaching dispute about the status of, and appropriate attitude toward what
the halakhic authorities take to be the halakhic tradition in their hands.[1] Traditionalists
insist that the halakhic tradition is at all times binding. No one, not even
the Great Sanhedrin, has the authority to overturn an existing ruling.
Halakha, they hold, develops and expands by accummulation, but is never
revised. Former
rulings are never overturned. From a traditionalist perspective, innovation is
wholly reserved for, and limited to halakhic lacunae.[2] As
Tosefta, Eduyot states forcefully, the only reason for preserving
rejected minority opinions on record is to ensure that they remain forever
rejected. Once a vote is taken the matter, is considered by traditionalists to
be settled once and for all.
Antitraditionalists
(as I have inelegantly dubbed them) maintain, by contrast, that it is the
religious duty of the halakhic authorities of each generation not only to
transmit and add to the received halakhic system, but to constantly review and
revise it as they fit. As Mishna, Eduyot puts it, equally forcefully, rejected
minority opinions remain on record, just in case a future Bet Din see fit to revise them. Both schools of
thought insist that the halakhic tradition be taken with utmost seriousness,
but differ as to what taking seriously means in this respect. For
traditionalists, it is to study it carefully and abide by it without question;
for antitraditionalists, it is to do so just as carefully, but with a view to
exposing its defects, and, as the need arises, to putting them right. The
dispute is explored and analyzed in considerable detail in the book (pp.
51-110), with special emphasis on the Jabne stories, and is further extended in
a later publication devoted to the Bet Shammai and Bet Hillel disputes.[3]
I then turn (pp. 111-62) to discuss the amoraic level of halakhic discourse,
found, in its most developed form in the Bavli. Here too one finds many
declarative and aggadic passages that in similar fashion explore, dramatize and
meditate upon issues pertaining to the nature of Torah-study and halakhic
development. But the Bavli has much more to offer. Like the Yerushalmi, but
unlike any antecedent tannaitic document, the Bavli is fashioned as an
ordered series of detailed, blow-by-blow responses to an earlier, authoritative
rabbinic text, the Mishna. The Gemara[4]
ponders, reconstructs and renders explicit the complex lines of reasoning that
supposedly led its predecessors to their conclusions, and continues vigorously
from the point the prior documents leave off. The narrative forms adopted in
its discursive portions resemble those of an elaborate, at times laborious,
protocol, normally accompanied by a clear, dispassionate running commentary.
Even if its framers had intended to produce no more than an unreflective
chronicle of amoraic learning, the Bavli would still be considered a rich
source for the study of early rabbinic epistemology. The Bavli, however, hardly
poses as an innocent, unassuming chronicle, nor can it be assumed to speak in one
voice. It impresses one as being first and foremost a didactic work, and,
therefore, an extraordinarily normative one, designed to convey a carefully
crafted vision of talmud-Torah. The framers of the Bavli offer their
reader punctilious descriptions of exemplary batei midrash in and out of
session. They assume the roles of anonymous narrator and moderator, patiently
indicating who, and what was asked, and who, and what was answered, who cited
whom, whose opinion was accepted and whose rejected, and all with a compact and
extraordinarily uniform vocabulary of logical connectives and inventory of
polemic moves. The reader is implicitly urged to study and ultimately to
imitate the way they describe themselves and their forerunners keenly
negotiating with their libraries and with each other. If one seeks evidence of
a talmudic theory, or theories of Torah-study in operation, it is here,
in the Bavli's narratives of reconstructed deliberation and dispute, that we
should first look.
Given
the way the Bavli presents itself, as a detailed study of so vast a body
of tannaitic halakhic writings, and given the fierce
traditionalist-antitraditionalist dispute concerning the epistemic and halakhic
standing of such legacies contained within it, it is only natural to ask ask
how the Bavli stands with regard to the
traditionalist-antitraditionalist dichotomy. To do so is to ask, first and
foremost, whether, and to what extent can its first-order narratives of amoraic
response to what is described therein as received tannaitic opinion be said to arguably premise one of the two
antithetical positions.
In theory the differences should be visible. On a traditionalist showing, an amora will never question an authentic tannaitic tradition. He may, of course, doubt its authenticity or ponder its meaning, and, subsequently, once satisfied, may even try to work it into a broader system, but, once it is understood, he will never, ever call it into question. Given a tannaitic statement A, an amora inclined towards traditionalism may ask "What is meant by A?", "To which cases was A meant to apply?", "To which additional cases can it be said to be relevant?", "To which broader issues may it be said to relate?", he may ponder the consistency of A with other tannaitic statements, but, unlike the antitraditionalist, it is unthinkable that he will ever ask "Is A a true or viable edict?". An amora so inclined might contest a colleague's understanding of a reliable tannaitic source, but never the source itself[5].
The kind of sugyot around which one would expect traditionalist and antitraditionalist redactors to differ most conspicuously are those devoted to negotiating apparent inconsistencies between tannaitic and amoraic opinions. These are cases, commonplace throughout the Bavli and Yerushalmi, in which a well-formed, articulated amoraic position is cited and then challenged by reports of seemingly contrary tannaitic opinion. For a traditionalist, the latter-day, amoraic view will always be the one rendered problematic when faced with such a challenge. Tannaim may disagree with one another (as can amoraim among themselves), but the only way, according to the traditionalist, that an amora can be said to contest a tanna is by aligning himself with another tanna. Hence, whenever a traditionalist cites a tannaitic source with reference to an amoraic declaration, it will always be with a view to confirming or trouble-shooting the latter[6]. For the antitraditionalist, by contrast, confirmation or criticism may, in principle, go either way. At any one time, antitraditionalists will be as respectfully skeptical of former documents, as they are hesitant and self-doubting with regard to their own opinions and those of their peers. Still in the course of a prudently antitraditionalist study-session, the direction of questioning will normally be from new to old, from amoraic to tannaitic rather than vice versa. The antitraditionalist forms his own halakhic opinions by seriously trouble-shooting those of his predecessors. Once he has tentatively made up his mind, and hesitantly boasts a system of his own, he will naturally regard it as superior to whatever earlier systems he had critically considered in the course of its formation. From his point of view, when the two are confronted, it will normally be for the earlier system to answer to the later one. One would, therefore, expect members of the two schools of thought to conduct and narrate such transgenerational confrontations very differently. However, even here, the talmudic text is far less unequivocal than we would have liked it to be. Even in the case of frontal confrontations between amoraic declaration and tannaitic verdict it is not always easy to decide which of the two texts is the framer of the sugya questioning by means of the other - certainly for those who, like the present author, were brought up to interpret them along traditionalist lines almost instinctively.
1. Introducing Berakhot 19b
The
Bavli introduces such transgenerational confrontations by means of the words
"meitivi" (a response was offered; an objection was raised) or
"eitivei" (he offered in response; he raised the following
objection)[7]. At first blush, both the meaning of the terms and the way they are
found to function in the text seem to favor a traditionalist approach. The very
terms meitivi and eitivei imply that in order to render a
latter-day amoraic opinion problematic, it is enough to cite a tannaitic source
that allegedly claims, implies or premises the contrary. The Bavli contains
over eleven-hundred transgenerational confrontations, of which
six-hundred-fifty or so are introduced by meitivi[8]. In more than sixty of them the
confrontation results in the Bavli declaring the amoraic position in question
"problematic" (teyuvta) and in about half of these, down-right
refuted (a ‘double’ teyuvta)[9]. Although the fatality rate is relatively
low – lower than 4½% - in the Bavli's world of discourse, an
amoraic statement is in real jeopardy when found to be discordant with a
tannaitic text. The opposite, though, seems never to be the case. Nowhere is a
tannaitic statement ever outwardly declared refuted or rejected as the result
of a meitivi-type confrontation.[10] When discordant amoraic and tannaitic statements are confronted, the
Bavli appears to adopt a clear traditionalist stance; always deeming the former
potentially at fault and liable to be rejected.
But does the
inner logic of such negotiations always lend itself to the marked
traditionalist idiom of the way they are narrated? Are all apparent
inconsistencies between tannaitic and amoraic statements dealt with in practice
as if it is obvious that the latter are always at fault? A reasonably reliable
method for determining a person's understanding of a problem is to look at the
way he or she elects to solve it. It stands to reason that if an incongruity
between two texts is deemed a problem for one of them, it will be the one
deemed problematic that will normally be modified, limited or rejected. (In
other words, it is generally the case that the remedy is applied to the wound.)
And it is here that one can frequently detect a disparity between what the
Bavli says it does and what it seems actually to be doing – for as a matter of
course, it is most often the tannaitic, rather than the amoraic text that ends
up suffering the consequences of the meitivi challenge. Contrary to the
traditionalist rhetoric of meitivi-type objections, the ways in which
they are met and dealt with in practice often attest to what appears to be a
boldly antitraditionalist mindset.
In
what follows I shall argue even further that the discrepancies between the form
and content of many of the Bavli's narratives of transgenerational discourse
are arguably contrived and deliberate; that their framers' basic attitude to
these confrontations is antitraditionalist, but that, for some reason, they
sought not to make this immediately apparent. The Bavli, I shall argue, in its
halakhic discourse, contains a clear and central, if deliberately disguised,
antitraditionalist voice. I do so by looking closely at what I believe is the
Bavli's own paradigmatic model of such a confrontation, its textbook example as
it were of a transgenerational give and take.
The
confrontation in question is related in Bavli, Berakhot 19b-20a as part
of the amoraic discussion of Mishna, Berakhot 3:1 which rules as follows:
One whose dead (relative) lies before him[11] is exempt from the recital of the shema
and from the tefillah and from tefillin and from all precepts
laid down in the Torah. With regard to the bearers of the bier and those who relieve
them (in carrying it to the grave) and those who relieve them again, whether in
front of the bier (having yet to carry) or behind the bier (and having done so
already) - those in front of the bier, if they are still required, are exempt;
but those behind the bier, even if still required, are not exempt. Both,
however, are exempt from saying the tefillah. When they have buried the
dead and returned (from the grave), if they have time to begin and finish (the shema)
before forming a row[12], they should begin, but if not they should
not begin. As for those who stand in the row, those on the inside[13] are exempt, but those on the outside are
not exempt.
The
Mishna does not explain why active participation at a funeral entails a
suspension of other religious duties. It simply states that it does, and goes
on to detail to whom it applies. Now, when one religious duty takes precedence
over another it is usually for a reason. What meta-halakhic principle is at
play here? A possible candidate is the talmudic principle that a person engaged
in the performance of one mitzva, is exempt from others[14]. The problem is that unlike the mourner's
halakhic duty to attend to his dead relative, one's obligation to carry the
bier and to form the row (or to listen to the funeral speeches mentioned by the
Tosefta) are not mitzvot of the Torah. They are at most rabbinic edicts
that, of themselves, can hardly be thought to merit temporary suspension from
major religious duties, such as tefillin, that are grounded in the Torah itself.
The reason for the exemption seems, in this case, to have to do with a general
obligation to pay respect for the dead - mipnei kevod ha-met. And
although Mishna, Berakhot gives no reason for its ruling, in a parallel
passage, one of the Minor Tractates does suggest quite clearly that kevod
ha-met is the principle at play[15].
But
if that be the case, what of respect for the living? To what extent, one is
inclined to ask, is a person supposed to defer or disobey "precepts laid
down in the Torah" for fear of disgracing, embarrassing, or hurting the
feelings of a living, fellow human? Does the halakha consider the dead and the
living to be analogous in this respect? Possibly motivated by such questions,
the Gemara, begins its discussion by citing the following beraita (which
is a slightly modified rendition of the Tosefta's version of the Mishna under
consideration):
Our Rabbis taught[16]: The row(s) that can see inside [are]
exempt, but [those] which cannot see inside [are] not exempt. R. Yehuda said:
Those who come on account of the mourner are exempt, but those who come
for their own purposes are not exempt.
This additional source
establishes a subtle difference between the rituals performed before and after
the actual burial. Carrying the bier and attending the funeral speeches
(mentioned by the Tosefta) postpone and supersede other religious duties
because in performing them respect is being paid to the deceased. The beraita,
however, implies that the exemption granted to participants in the rows formed
after the burial is granted, at least according to R. Yehuda, by virtue of the
respect they are paying to the living mourner. By citing the beraita -
for which there seems to me to be no other reason - the framer of the sugya
subtly, and surreptitiously suggests that a general tannaitic principle may be
at work here, according to which the obligation to respect any human being -
dead or alive - overrides other religious duties. But he does so inaudibly,
sheerly by implication, without even hinting at it openly. The two tannaitic
texts are set side by side for the readers to reach their own conclusions as it
were.
This
is not to say that the notion of respect is not discussed. On the contrary, the
Gemara's discussion of the Mishna focuses almost entirely on questions related
to respect. But although various of aspects of human dignity are discussed in
some detail, the word "respect" itself is never specifically
associated with the Mishna or the above-quoted beraita. By the time the
discussion reaches its climax on fol. 19a, the issue of human dignity is
already "in the air", but in a manner seemingly unrelated to the two
main tannaitic documents under consideration. One has to be well-acquainted
with the Mishna's two other parallels to realize that both the Mishna and beraita
bear decisively on the question of the relative weight of the obligation of
respecting human dignity in comparison to other religious duties (if for the
tannaitic authorities it was indeed ever a question). If one is not aware of
the parallels, the following statement, attributed to the first generation
amora Rav, will not appear to be at all related to the Mishna. The less
advanced student of the Talmud will in all probability pass it by without
making the connection at all; associating its appearance at best with the
Gemara's prior, seemingly unrelated discussion of one's obligation to respect
one's Masters - a point we shall return to shortly. But for more seasoned students who are aware of the parallels, the
statement attributed to Rav does more than merely relate to the Mishna. Read in
conjunction with the beraita, as the framer of the sugya would
have them do, the statement attributed to the first generation amora Rav,
appears to assert the very opposite: namely, that one should always attend to
one's ritual duties without delay, even at the cost of publicly disgracing
oneself, or at the cost of having to act disrespectfully even towards one's
Master! In other words, if the Mishna is taken to assert that respect for the
dead is to override all religious duties, and if the beraita is supposed
to imply that in this respect the dead and the living are analogous, then Rav's
ruling squarely contradicts them.
R. Yehuda said in the name of Rav: If one
discovers mixed kinds[17] in his garment, he should take it off even
in the street. What is the reason? [it says:] "There is no wisdom nor
understanding nor counsel against the Lord" (Prov. 21:30); wherever a
profanation of God's name is involved no respect is paid (even) to a teacher[18].
Because the framer of the sugya
says nothing about the possible relationship that Rav's statement might
bear to the Mishna and/or to the beraita, it is not at all clear at the
outset how he intends it to be understood. Are we to understand it as not
necessarily contesting the Mishna's ruling regarding the dead, and as insisting
only that respect for the living should under no circumstances take
precedence over other religious duties? For those aware of the fact that the
Mishna is about respect for the dead, Rav's stated position would then
imply that, if the Mishna be maintained, then respect for the dead must be
viewed as a unique and limited sub-category of respect that cannot be extended
to the living. However, in the course of the Bavli's immediate discussion of
Rav's statement, it swiftly becomes apparent (a) that Rav principle is
understood to extend to the dead, and therefore, by implication, does
contradict the Mishna; and (b) that the fact that it contradicts the Mishna is
passed over by the framer of the sugya in utter silence. In fact, from
the moment Rav's principle is cited, all mention of both the Mishna and beraita
are dropped. But although the discrepancy between Rav's statement and the two
tannaitic texts previously under discussion is passed over by the s'tam[19] without a word, he proceeds to confront it
energetically with a series of five other texts of tannaitic origin, all of
which also appear to contradict it quite clearly[20]. And it is here that the series of meitivi-type
confrontations I wish to discuss are conducted.
We
are dealing, then, with a general amoraic assertion, placed by the framer of
the sugya in the immediate context of two major tannaitic sources, one
of them: the very Mishna under discussion, with which it is, though it is not
actually said to be, clearly at variance, and which is then openly contrasted
with, a series of five other, equally conflicting, tannaitic sources as
follows:
Meitivi. (Says the beraita:) If they have buried the body and are
returning, and there are two ways to go, one (ritually) pure and the other
impure[21], if [the bereaved heading the procession]
goes by the pure one they go with him by the pure one, and if he goes by the
impure one they (and with them even the priests) go with him by the impure one,
out of respect for him[22]. Why (is this so)? Why not say: "There
is no wisdom nor understanding nor counsel against the Lord" (and hence:
wherever a profanation of God's name is involved no respect is paid to a
teacher)? R. Abba explained the statement to refer to a bet ha-p'ras[23], which is declared impure only by the
rabbis (but not by the Torah itself); for R. Yehuda has said in the name of
Shmuel: A man may blow in front of him (in order to scatter the small bones) in
a bet ha-p'ras and proceed (without fear of defilement). And R. Yehuda
b. Ashi also said in the name of Rav: A bet ha-p'ras which has been
well-trodden is pure.
The
apparent incongruity between the statement cited by R. Yehuda in the name of
Rav and the beraita leveled against it is harmonized away by R. Abba (a
disciple of R. Yehuda) by retaining Rav's latter-day opinion and radically
limiting the tannaitic ruling of the beraita to the case of a bet ha-p'ras - a
particular type of burial site which, on the authority of both R. Yehuda and
Rav, does not involve the sort of impurity prohibited of priests by the Torah
itself. We began with an
amoraic statement in conflict with a tannaitic text, and end with harmony
achieved by a significant modification of the latter's straightforward meaning.
And the pattern repeats itself. The four additional tannaitic texts cited in
contrast to Rav's statement, are met by precisely the same procedure.
"Come and hear (another beraita)", continues the anonymous s'tam,
For R. Elazar b. Zadok said: We (even the priests!) used to leap
over coffins containing bodies to greet Israelite kings (...) Why (is
this so)? Why not say: "There is no wisdom nor understanding nor counsel
against the Lord" (and hence: wherever a profanation of God's name is
involved no respect is paid to a teacher)? [It is in accord with the dictum of
Raba] For Raba said: It is a rule of the Torah that a 'tent'[24] which has a
hollow space of a handbreadth (between its outside and what it contains) forms
a partition against impurity, but if it has not a hollow space of a handbreadth
it forms no partition against impurity[25]. Now most
coffins do have a space of a handbreadth, but [the rabbis] decreed that those
which have such a space [should form no partition] for fear that they should be
confused with those which do not have such space. Still, where respect to kings
was involved they did not enforce the decree.
Come and hear
(yet another beraita): "Great is human dignity, since it overrides
negative precepts of the Torah"[26]. Why should it?
Why not say: "There is no
wisdom nor understanding nor counsel against the Lord"? Rav b. Shaba
explained the beraita in the presence of R. Kahana to refer only to the
(one, single) negative precept "thou shalt not deviate [from the sentence
which they shall tell thee, to the right hand or to the left]" (Deut.
17:11)[27]. They laughed at
him: (even so) the negative precept of "thou shalt not deviate" is
itself from the Torah (and, therefore, the objection still stands)! Said R.
Kahana: If a great man makes a statement you should not laugh at him. All the
ordinances of the rabbis were based by them on the prohibition of "thou
shalt not deviate", but where the question of [human] dignity is
concerned, the rabbis permitted it.
Once
again, the tannaitic text is reinterpreted so as to comply completely with
Rav's latter-day principle. (This time by two amoraim who functioned five
generations after its alleged author.) The strategy is the same as before: to
argue that Rav has really said nothing new. All have always agreed, the s'tam
implies, that concerns for human dignity are powerless when the actual
prohibitions of the Torah are involved. Only with respect to their own
latter-day interdictions were the rabbis willing to allow considerations of
respect to take precedence. With this, we are led to understand, Rav has no
quarrel, and the appearance of perfect transgenerational harmony is duly, if
somewhat artificially preserved.
But at a deeper, more subtle level
the s'tam seems to be calling his own bluff. For hard as he may try, he
knows very well that his less naive readers will not ignore or forget the
Mishna or Tosefta. On the contrary, the greater his effort invested in
harmonizing Rav's statement with other seemingly conflicting tannaitic texts,
harder felt is the total absence of a similar treatment of the Mishna and
Tosefta. For those aware of their origins and original contexts, they present
equally clear and authoritative cases of tannaitic rulings that sanction
transgressions of "all the
precepts laid down in the Torah"
in the name of respect, for both the dead (Mishna) and the living (Tosefta).
The conflict between Rav's ruling and the two texts becomes more and more
apparent as challenges to it from other tannaitic quarters are presented and
warded off. I find it extremely
hard to believe that the framer of the sugya was unaware of his
omission, and shall suggest further down that both the build-up of the tension
and the fact that it is passed over in utter silence are intentional. My claim shall be that the disturbing
presence of the Mishna and Tosefta, persisting ignored in the background,
serves, intentionally, to subtly lay bare the unseriousness of the entire
harmonization project. It is as if the s'tam was declaring: 'I do not object to the idea that Rav's
ruling was in fact revolutionary, I only object to presenting it as such. And
as long as the beginners remain unaware of what I'm doing, I don't mind leaving
a contradicting tannaitic text unattended'! But back to the sugya
itself.
The questioning and answering goes
on. The next case is different, however, because it involves the overriding, in
the name of human dignity, of a negative precept that cannot, on any count, be
dismissed as involving no more than a rabbinic injunction.
Come and hear,
(says the beraita): (It
says:) "[Thou shalt not see thy brother's ox or his sheep go astray] and
hide thyself from (ignore) them [thy shalt surely bring them back to thy
brother]" (Deut. 22: 1, 4) -
(From the positive phrasing of the negative precept we learn that) there are
times when you mayest ignore them and times when thou mayest not ignore them.
How so? If [the person who sees the animal] is a priest and [the animal] is in
a graveyard, or if he is an elder and it is not in accordance with his dignity
(to pursue or tend to the animal), or if his own work was greater than that of
his fellow[28]. Therefore it is
said "ignore". But
why so? Why not say: "There is no wisdom nor understanding nor counsel
against the Lord"? The case is different there, because it says expressly:
"and hide thyself from (ignore) them".
In other words, this apparent
contradiction to Rav's principle is avoided by portraying the beraita as
describing not a matter of principle, but a unique exception to the rule
specifically required by the Torah. Why then, asks the Gemara, is it regarded
an exception? Why don't we take this particular teaching of the Torah as the
basis for deriving the general rule to the conclusion, contrary to Rav, that
showing respect indeed always overrides negative precepts of the Torah?
Because, the Gemara answers, of the technical reason that one cannot derive a
ruling concerning matters of ritual from one related merely to property. The
theoretical possibility of using the tannaitic materials to construct a general
system rival to the one proposed by Rav, is considered, and firmly rejected -
rather unceremoniously, one must admit.
So
far the four tannaitic sources brought against Rav have all dealt exclusively
with respect payable to the living. Hence one could still argue that Rav's
principle was perhaps meant to be understood not to apply to respect for the
dead, and, therefore, not to contradict the Mishna and its parallels. But the
impression is abruptly dispelled by the fifth and final ta shema.
Come and hear, (says the beraita): (It says:) "[He shall not make
himself impure for his father, or for his mother, for his brother,] or for his
sister[, when they die]" (Num. 6:7) What does this teach us? Suppose he[29] was on his way to killing his Paschal Lamb
or to circumcising his son when he heard that a near relative had died, am I to
say that he should go back and defile himself? You say, he should not defile
himself[30]. Shall I say, therefore, that just as he
does not defile himself for them, so he should not defile himself for a met
mitzva[31]? It says significantly: "or for his
sister": [only] for his sister he does not defile himself but he does
defile himself for a met mitzva. But why should this be? Why not apply
the rule: "There is no wisdom nor understanding nor counsel against the
Lord"? The case is different here, because it is written expressly
"or for his sister".
Again, the apparent
contradiction between Rav's principle and the ruling recorded by the beraita
is avoided by interpreting the latter as describing not a matter of principle,
but a singular exception to the rule - Rav's rule of course - specifically
required by Scripture. In this way the last two beraitot are made to
work in favor of Rav's statement. Had a rule different from that of Rav been
known to apply, namely, that transgressions of the Torah be permitted in order
to avoid disrespect, the Torah would not have needed to issue special rulings
with regard to the elderly finder of a misplaced animal or the nazirite priest.
The exceptions, as it were, are taken to prove, rather than disprove
Rav’s ruling. This is a typical and standard argument in rabbinic midrash
halakha. The Torah does not waste its words. It should be read in ways that
presuppose as far as possible a complete absence of contradiction, redundancy
or arbitrariness. If the Torah goes to the trouble of explicitly stating or
suggesting a particular ruling, it is, therefore, either to state an exception,
and in doing so to affirm the rule, or to establish a paradigm. The latter
option, as in the previous passage, is here also briefly considered and
rejected, and Rav's initial ruling is left intact.
As
noted, this last objection raised against Rav's ruling is highly significant
because of the conflation it presupposes between acting respectfully towards
the dead and the living, which, as we have seen, places it inevitably at
variance with both the Mishna and Tosefta under consideration – of which, to
repeat, not a word is said. When considered in terms of its general context, as
part of the discussion of the Mishna under whose heading it is introduced, the
citation of Rav's principle and its subsequent examination constitute, it seems
to me, an intriguing (if typical) case of deliberately unannounced
transgenerational dissent. While the apparent incongruities it exhibits
with relation to five other tannaitic sources are energetically pursued and
resolved (more on their resolution immediately), the fact that Rav's position
turns out to be comparably incompatible with the Mishna itself is passed over
in utter silence.
2. The Logic and Rhetoric of Transgenerational Negotiation
Let
us briefly review how this is achieved. The Mishna rules, without explaining
why, that the mourners and active participants in a burial service are exempt
"from all precepts laid down in the Torah". Parallel sources clearly
indicate that the reason for the deferment is kevod ha-met, respect
for the dead. Nowhere throughout its discussion of the Mishna does the Gemara
explicitly attribute the notion of respect for the dead specifically to the
Mishna's ruling, but it certainly does so implicitly[32]. Read thus, the implications are obvious:
if respect for the dead is the reason for partaking in burial services, and if,
according to the Mishna, such participation entails an exemption "from all
precepts laid down in the Torah", then the Mishna inevitable premises a
principle that is squarely opposed to the one attributed to Rav. Moreover, the
fact that Rav's statement is eventually found to survive the meitivi
confrontations with the five other tannaitic sources almost intact[33], clearly suggests that, in the s'tam's
opinion, the Mishna is not merely contradicted, but is actually superseded by
Rav's ruling[34]! I realize that this is a bold conclusion
that will come as a shock to many students of the Talmud, especially those of
traditional schooling like myself. But it is unavoidable. It seems quite clear
to me that the framer of the sugya goes to considerable lengths in order
to intimate it. The sugya, in both its content and inner logic, clearly
suggest that a substantially antitraditionalist attitude is adopted toward the
Mishna on a significant matter of meta-halakhic principle.
Why,
then, does the s'tam seem so reluctant to discuss, or even state his
strategy openly? Why do the larger contours of the sugya read as if a
major point is being made and concealed at one and the same time? It is as if
the sugya was constructed by a confident, yet covert antitraditionalist
who, for some reason, is reluctant, to articulate the basic drift of the sugya
he is framing. It is as if the sugya was deliberately fashioned to
ensure that only the most advanced students should get its main point.
And
the same goes for the meitivi confrontations themselves. Here too, a
closer look reveals a sharp disparity between what is said and what is being
done; between the ways in which the discrepancies between Rav's statement and
the five tannaitic texts are in fact negotiated, and the rhetoric with which
such negotiations are usually related.
As
noted at the outset, we expect traditionalists and antitraditionalists to
conduct meitivi-type confrontations, For traditionalists, an apparent
discrepancy between an amoraic and a tannaitic ruling will always, without
exception, be interpreted as constituting a problem for the former. It is for
the amora, or his discursive representatives, either to convincingly explain
the discrepancy away, or to withdraw his statement. For traditionalists, the
very word "meitivi" cannot mean anything but 'how is it
possible for the amora in question to say what he says in view of a tannaitic
source that quite clearly claims the opposite?' And although a traditionalist
may on occasion end up resolving such a transgenerational discrepancy by
suggesting that the tannaitic source should be interpreted differently, he will
never, ever initially view it as a challenge to, or criticism of the tannaitic
source.
The
very mark of antitraditionalism, by contrast, is that latter-day positions are
frequently acquired as a result of critically rethinking, and subsequently
modifying or rejecting earlier ones. Therefore, in the event of apparent
discordance between an authentic and uncorrupted tannaitic ruling and an
amoraic position, an antitraditionalist may very well decide to view the
tannaitic ruling as the defective of the two. In which case, he will have, in
theory, two options: either to declare the tannaitic source superseded in the
light of the more recent amoraic edict, or to preserve it by harmonizing it
with the amoraic ruling. As noted, in meitivi-type situations the Bavli opts
exclusively for the latter. Nowhere is a tannaitic source declared refuted,
rejected or superseded by virtue of an amoraic statement to the contrary.[35] But if that is the case, it seems
near-impossible to distinguish between traditionalist and antitraditionalist
framers of even meitivi, transgenerational confrontations. If the former
permit themselves on occasion to reinterpret the tannaitic sources involved,
and the latter refrain from ever explicitly rejecting them, and if members of
neither school of thought actually state which of the texts involved they
consider problematic, how is it ever possible to distinguish between them?
At
least with regard to the very last point - that of expressly pointing to the
text considered by the framer of the sugya to be the one open to
question - the sugya in Berakhot, quite typical as it is, does
have something quite unique to offer. Unlike any other meitivi-type
confrontation known to me, the anonymous s'tam repeatedly and explicitly
states his difficulty. "Why is this so?", he asks of each of the five
tannaitic sources supposedly leveled against Rav, why isn't the rule attributed
to Rav - that 'There is no wisdom nor understanding nor counsel against the
Lord' - also applied here[36]? Each of the tannaitic texts, in other
words, seems to be expressly questioned by the s'tam in the light of
Rav's ruling, rather than vice versa. Here, the s'tam can be understood
to be directing queries against what seems to be a coherent tannaitic program,
rather than a series of objections to an amoraic statement leveled from
different tannaitic quarters. Given Rav's general ruling, he puzzles,
what are we to make of these tannaitic texts? Of course, there are ways to
render the s'tam's question along customary traditionalist lines. Still,
when taken in conjunction with the other remarkable features of this sugya,
such traditionalist renderings of the s'tam's wholly unique articulation
will sound increasingly unconvincing[37].
The
five tannaitic texts confronted by Rav's principle represent four genres of
halakhic literature. They include a specific tannaitic ruling (to accompany the
mourner, even when he chooses an unclean way, "out of respect for
him"); a reliable tannaitic record of apparently uncontested precedent
(that of priests leaping over coffins containing bodies in order to show
respect for kings); a tannaitic statement of a general meta-halakhic principle
("Great is human dignity, since it overrides negative precepts of the
Torah"); and two evidently undisputed tannaitic midrashei halakha
(that a person need not disgrace himself in order to return another person's
lost animal, and that nazirites, even if they are High Priests, are obliged to
defile themselves for the sake of attending to a met mitzva). Read, as
the framer of the sugya initially intended us to understand them, and
taken together with the Mishna and Tosefta, as the wider reaches of the sugya
imply that we should, the five texts leveled against Rav's ruling clearly
attest to the existence and wide application of a general tannaitic
meta-halakhic principle, quite at odds with that of Rav, according to which
considerations related to the respect and dignity of both the dead and the
living generally take precedence over other religious duties, including
precepts of the Torah itself.
The
sugya, however, is not about the formation of Rav's principle. It
is not about the reasons that Rav and his generation might have had for
departing from the opinion of their predecessors, or for adopting the views
they had come to accept. Meitivi confrontations are not about the dynamics
of halakhic development. They function as rearguard mop-ups of
transgenerational incongruities. That is why they are so important for our
present concerns. For the framer of the sugya, Rav's principle is a
given, as are the five tannaitic sources with which it is confronted (and the
Mishna and Tosefta with which confrontation is so cannily avoided). But he
appears to have decided to deal with the crisis by a curious and incoherent
combination of a traditionalist and antitraditionalist strategies. On the one
hand, he seems to have decided in advance that none of the tannaitic texts
explicitly confronted will be actually discarded or even outwardly modified in
the process. On the other hand, he seems also to have decided that Rav's
position will be retained as it stands come what may. The only way he can
achieve both objectives concurrently is by reinterpreting all the tannaitic
materials involved in ways that render them inoffensive to Rav's position. He
thus succeeds in avoiding both extreme purist responses. Despite the apparently
conclusive tannaitic evidence against it, Rav's opinion is not declared refuted
as is sometimes the outcome of meitivi confrontations. On the other
hand, despite the decision to retain the amoraic ruling, the confrontations and
their resolution succeed in carrying no overt antitraditionalist overtones. And
yet from a purely halakhic point of view, it is Rav ruling that carries the day
in the face of obvious and principled tannaitic opposition. The supposedly
“middle way” adopted by the s'tam enables him to enjoy the best of both
worlds: to avoid all explicit involvement in the
traditionalist/antitraditionalist dispute, and at the same time to remain an
antitraditionalist while sounding as if he isn’t.
The
s'tam succeeds in performing a bold antitraditionalist move - just how
bold we shall see immediately - but to do so with little chance of it ever
being comprehended as such, except by the most well-versed and attentive of his
readers. This in itself does not yet make this particular sugya unique.
On the contrary, in this respect it is quite typical of its kind. Its
uniqueness resides, in my opinion, in the way it subtly gives the game away
while playing it. Unlike any other meitivi-type confrontation I have
studied, this particular sugya strikes me as being self-consciously and
uniquely paradigmatic. It appears to have been deliberately set up with a view
to drawing attention to, and partly dispelling the confusion created by the
type of double-talk it so nicely exemplifies. It does so by a variety of means:
substantial, contextual, rhetorical - all cunningly aimed at only the most
advanced level of readership. But to appreciate both the extent of its
antitraditionalism and the almost didactic quality of its self-exposure we need
to look briefly again at the ways the incongruities between Rav's ruling and
the five tannaitic texts are harmonized away – especially the third.
Harmonization
of the first three is achieved by marginally (and surreptitiously) limiting
Rav's ruling to transgressions of scriptural religious duties, while radically
limiting the tannaitic sources to scribal edicts only. In this respect, it is
surely the third beraita that undergoes the most radical reinterpretation.
The third beraita states quite explicitly that care for human dignity is
so great that "it overrides
negative precepts of the Torah". No, explains Rav b. Shaba, causing
his colleagues to snicker, not "negative precepts of the Torah" in general, but only one such precept -
namely, the Torah's negative commandment not to disobey such Scribal decrees of
the kind that indeed lack Scriptural status! The radicalism, some might even
say the sheer chutzpah, of the Bavli's proposed interpretation of this
particular tannaitic principle - indeed the radicalism that permeates the
entire sugya - becomes even more apparent when one looks at earlier
employments of the very same principle by the Yerushalmi. The Bavli, I should
add immediately, in keeping with its reading here, does in fact apply it
consistently only to Scribal decrees[38].
3. Yerushalmi and Bavli Compared
The
Yerushalmi cites and discusses slightly different versions of the principle on
three separate occasions. On two of them it is introduced in the course of
discussing the first of the five beraitot confronted with Rav by the
Bavli. "What is meant by requiring a priest to defile himself out of
respect for the many[39]?", asks Yerushalmi, Berakhot iii 6b and Nazir vii
56a,
We have learnt (in the beraita): If
there were two (equally) suited ways, one long and pure, and the other shorter
but impure, if the majority take the long one, he should take the long one, and
if not, he should take the short one (with them) out of respect for the
majority.
Notice, that, unlike the Bavli's
version of the beraita, the setting here is not necessarily that of a
burial service. In fact, to the embarrassment of several commentators, the
Yerushalmi's version does not even indicate that the priest and his colleagues
were at all on their way to perform a religious duty[40]. The issue for the Yerushalmi appears
simply to be that of permitting a priest to defile himself in order to avoid
hurting the feelings of his co-travelers, regardless for the reasons or
destination of their joint excursion. But of what level of impurity are we
speaking? "So far", the Yerushalmi goes on to ask, "have we
spoken only of impurity due to Scribal decree?",
Does [the same principle] also apply to
impurity prohibited by the words of the Torah? It (does, and) follows from the
saying of R. Zeira: "Great is the dignity of the many, since it
temporarily overrides (a) negative precept[s][41]". Ada said, (therefore, a priest should follow the many along the
impure path) even in the case of impurity prohibited by the words of the Torah.
Although
the saying, attributed by the Yerushalmi to R. Zeira, does not ever explicitly
say, as does the version cited by the Bavli, that the negative precept(s) in
question are indeed those of the Torah, it is understood throughout the
Yerushalmi, without exception[42], to mean precisely that! In other words,
when Rav b. Shaba is reputed by the Bavli to have "explained the dictum in
the presence of R. Kahana" two generations later, he may not have been
merely ignoring the theoretical possibility that the text might
actually mean what it says, but may have been overlooking the fact,
possibly willingly, that, at least in Palestinian halakhic discourse, the
dictum was indeed thus read. If anything, the Yerushalmi bears clear and
incontestable witness to the existence[43] of a school of thought, apparently
associated among second and third-generation amoraim with R. Zeira and
R. Ada, who, as a matter of (literary) fact, read the dictum, and apparently
acted upon it, very differently from what Rav b. Shaba would have us believe.
But
the Yerushalmi has more to offer that is relevant to the Bavli's meitivi-type
negotiation of Rav's principle than its very different reading of this
particular dictum. On the very question of the discovery of mixed kinds in
public, the case offered by Rav as a paradigmatic example of his principle,
Yerushalmi, Kilayim ix 32a records a debate that further emphasizes just
how strained are the Bavli's relentless attempts to harmonize Rav's teaching
with everything that supposedly went before it. The relevant passage reads as
follows:
One who was walking in the market-place and
found himself wearing mixed kinds. Two amoraim (debated the issue). One
said that it is prohibited (and therefore the garment must be removed immediately).
The other said that it is permitted (for him to go on wearing the garment until
he can remove it in the privacy of his home). The one who said that it is
prohibited maintains that [wearing mixed kinds] is (a transgression of) a law
of the Torah. The one who said it is permitted accords with R. Zeira who said
that great is human dignity that temporarily overrides a negative commandment.
Seeking to harmonize this
passage with the one in Bavli, Berakhot, traditional commentators
explain the dispute recorded here as if it were no more than a factual
disagreement[44]. The amora who prohibits and demands the
removal of the garment, they explain, is of the opinion that the mixed kinds in
question are of the sort prohibited by the Torah. His colleague, on the other
hand, believes that the mixed kinds in question are of the sort prohibited only
by Scribal decree, and therefore does not demand the removal of the garment in
the market-place. This, they add, is in accord with R. Zeira's principle,
which, in keeping with its rendition by the Bavli, supposedly allows (only)
transgressions of Scribal decrees in order not to offend the public or disgrace
oneself. Although such a reading of the debate succeeds in squaring it with the
Bavli's version of Rav's allegedly uncontested view on the matter, it does
little justice to the text of the Yerushalmi. On such a showing, the debate
claimed by the Yerushalmi to have obtained between the two amoraim is in
truth no debate at all. Both disputants agree that the sort of mixed kinds
prohibited by the Torah must be removed the moment they are discovered,
regardless of where one happens to be at the time, and that in the case of
mixed kinds prohibited only by Scribal decree, one may postpone their removal
in order to avoid inflicting, or suffering public disgrace. By reading the
Yerushalmi thus, two related objectives are achieved. First, Rav's ruling
regarding the discovery of mixed kinds in public - and, subsequently, his view
on the entire question of human dignity - remains uncontested in keeping with
the Bavli's keen efforts. Second, and again in keeping with the Bavli's
program, the realm of application of R. Zeira's principle is conveniently
limited to Scribal decrees. But as much as the framer of Bavli, Berakhot
19b might have liked Yerushalmi, Kilayim to comply with his agenda, such
a reading of the latter is implausible. For one thing, the Yerushalmi states
quite clearly that on the question of the discovery of mixed kinds in
the market-place - Rav's question - two Sages differed. As is often the
case in the Yerushalmi, the text that follows is not as lucidly and as
carefully redacted as we would have liked it be. Still, to interpret even the
Yerushalmi as announcing a difference of opinion only to mean that in truth the
two Sages merely differed in their understanding of the question is to
do real violence to the text. And in view of the Yerushalmi's other two
references of R. Zeira's principle, to limit its application here exclusively
to Scribal decrees is to render the Yerushalmi's various appeals to the
principle mutually inconsistent.
The compelling conclusion is that where the
Bavli goes to incredible lengths to present a harmonious transgenerational
front united around Rav's principle, the Yerushalmi does not display the
slightest uneasiness about presenting the field as deeply divided twice over.
According to the Yerushalmi, not only was the position, attributed by the Bavli
to Rav, directly disputed in its time, but its adversaries are said to have
justified their move by appealing to no other than R. Zeira's dictum. Again,
the Yerushalmi bears witness to the "real" existence of a very
different understanding of this dictum than the strained interpretation
provided by the Bavli. This time, however, it is not merely read differently
than in the Bavli, but is employed as an argument against the very position to
which the Bavli would have it conform!
In
view of these earlier sources, it seems rather unlikely that Bavli, Berakhot
19b could have been framed in genuine unawareness of there being real
opposition to Rav. On the other hand, the sugya, especially that part of
it devoted to Rav's ruling, by no means gives the impression of being confused,
or poorly edited. There is a distinctly contrived, structured, I would even say
didactic air about the entire text. The s'tam appears to know exactly
what is at stake, where he is going, and why he is going there. (Such hunches,
of course, are hard to demonstrate, let alone prove. But they do make good
methodological sense. We are always liable to miss something of importance by
attributing ignorance, innocence, sloppiness or confusion to the texts we seek
to understand before serious attempts at more charitable readings have proved
to fail). Assuming, then, that the Bavli is aware of the fact that attitudes
toward human dignity different from Rav's, such as those recorded by the
Yerushalmi, may well have originally motivated the tannaitic texts it
considers, and that Rav himself had knowingly formed his views in defiance of
these earlier systems of thought, what was to be achieved by such a
far-fetched, and, to an extent false, exercise in transgenerational
harmonizing? Why is the Bavli so eager to conceal disagreement where the
Yerushalmi seems quite content to display it? All the more so if, according to
the Yerushalmi, Rav's position remained contested among amoraim!
One
obvious difference between the Yerushalmi and the Bavli on the question of the
discovery of mixed kinds in public, is the former's apparent disinterest in resolving
it and making a ruling. On this particular question the Yerushalmi's objective
is no more than to describe and explain the two rival positions. The Bavli, on
the other hand, has apparently not only decided to resolve the issue, but to do
so in favor of an amora facing substantial tannaitic opposition and apparently
enjoying no known tannaitic support. This perhaps explains the great effort
invested by the Bavli in making the tannaitic texts seem to have
anticipated Rav's latter-day point of view. But while the two talmudim
do so differ in their approaches of the question of mixed kinds, their
differences can hardly account for the Bavli's feigned traditionalism. There
are at least two good reasons for not accepting the Bavli's obvious desire to
resolve the issue as a viable explanation of its equally obvious efforts to
conceal the opposition. First, traditionalists and antitraditionalists maintain
mutually exclusive positions. Hence one of two: had the sugya been
framed by a traditionalist, the halakha should not have been ruled in accord
with Rav's view in the first place; and had it been framed by an
antitraditionalist, the feigned traditionalism would have hardly been called
for. Why perform what looks like a decidedly bold antitraditionalist move while
doing your utmost to sound as if you're not?
Secondly,
although, in the case of the mixed kinds, the Yerushalmi does no more than to
note and explain the two conflicting views, there are several other cases of
transgenerational confrontation in which the Yerushalmi not only decides the
issue, but does so by ruling against the tannaitic sources in favor of amoraic
opinions[45]. In all these cases, however, and this is the important point, quite
unlike the Bavli, the Yerushalmi makes no effort at all to cover up its tracks.
The differences between the ways each of the two talmudim presents these
negotiations is quite striking.
It
is significant perhaps that the most clear and detailed meitivi-type
negotiation of this sort that the Yerushalmi has to offer, is contained in none
other than tractate Kilayim ix 32a in the passage immediately preceding
its account of the case of mixed kinds. Here too, as in Bavli, Berakhot 19b,
the amoraic position under consideration is one of Rav's oft-quoted rulings,
and here too it is confronted by a series of tannaitic texts that appear
clearly to assert the opposite. But apart from that, the two sugyot -
each of them absolutely typical of its kind - are worlds apart. Despite the
special transitional status granted to Rav by the Bavli (more on this below),
the difference between the two amoraic redactions remains stunning.
For
one thing the Yerushalmi does not, as a rule, announce the transgenerational
incongruities it discusses by a loaded term like the Bavli's "meitivi".
The introduction of an apparently contradicting tannaitic source is not
described as an "objection" to the amoraic position under
consideration. The term used to set forth each of the two-hundred-thirty or so
transgenerational confrontations conducted throughout the Yerushalmi is
completely neutral in this respect: "matnita (or matnitin) pliga
de-..." - which is simply to declare that "(the following)
tannaitic text ('Mishna') disagrees with ...". The difference, as we shall
see, is more than verbal, the Yerushalmi in truth seems to assume nothing in
advance.
The halakhic principle attributed to
Rav and discussed in Kilayim ix 32a is: "All that is prohibited for
appearance's sake is also forbidden when done privately"[46]. Six different tannaitic
texts are then introduced in quick succession:
(The following) [tannaitic
source][47] disagrees with Rav: One
should not use linen that is dyed black[48] to make a visible hem, but
it is permitted (to use such black tinted linen) in pillows and bed-covers[49].
A(nother) [tannaitic
source][50] (that) disagrees with Rav:
Should one's coins fall and scatter in front of an idol, one should not stoop
down to repossess them in order not to appear to be bowing to the idol, but, if
no one is present, it is permitted.
A(nother) [tannaitic source][51] (that) disagrees with Rav:
One should not touch one's mouth to a public fountain fashioned as a face (of a
false deity) in order not to appear to be kissing it, but if no one is present,
it is permitted.
(Yet) a(nother) [tannaitic
source][52] (that) disagrees with Rav:
One should not prepare a hole in the ground to receive the blood of a
slaughtered beast, but in confines of one's home it is permitted. He should not
do so in public (in the market place) in order not to appear a heretic[53].
A(nother) [tannaitic
source][54] (that) disagrees with Rav:
It is permitted (on the Sabbath) to lay out (in one's yard, garments that were
drenched by the rain in order to dry) in the sun, but not within view of
passers by.
A(nother) [tannaitic
source][55] (that) disagrees with Rav:
One should not pour water on the Sabbath (from one's yard) into the street
(even) through a four-cubit deep drain[56] (...) (However) R. Kapara
has taught that if no one is present, it is permitted.
No
attempt is made to explain the discrepancies away, or to seek for minority
views among the tannaitic sources that might conform to Rav's position. Despite
the fact that in this sugya, unlike that of the mixed kinds, the
Yerushalmi is working toward an halakhic decision, it shows not the slightest
inclination to harmonize the texts under consideration, gloss their
differences, or somehow argue them away. And even if the Yerushalmi does
presuppose Rav's special license to contest tannaitic opinion, it makes no
mention of it, and certainly refrains from rejecting Rav's, obviously, minority
view in favor of the uncontested tannaitic evidence mounted so clearly against
it. Rather, the Yerushalmi sums up the situation in one, short and potent
sentence, declaring simply and unceremoniously that:
All of these (beraitot) are
in disagreement with Rav, and (therefore?)[57] have no standing![58]
This is a matter very different from
the special privilege of disputing tannaitic opinion, granted to Rav by
the Bavli on occasion.[59] It is no longer a question of simply acknowledging
Rav's license to think differently from his predecessors, but of the framer of
the sugya ruling in his favor in the face of wide and varied
tannaitic opposition. To this end the Yerushalmi appears to have no qualms
about declaring bona fide tannaitic sources null and void. Once these
earlier documents are found to contradict Rav's ruling it is not the fate of our
understanding of them[60] that seems to be at stake,
but the fate of the documents themselves! And this is not the only case.
On six other occasions the Yerushalmi concludes such meitivi-type
confrontations with the same formula, similarly dismissing the tannaitic
sources in question in favor of the amoraic positions under consideration. The
Bavli never resolves a transgenerational conflict of views by outwardly
rejecting a tannaitic source. Still, despite the great pains to which the Bavli
goes to retain a strict traditionalist frame of discourse, we are left by both talmudim
with the same halakhic conclusions!
To
fully appreciate the discursive difference between the two talmudim in
this respect, let us look briefly at the way the very same principle of Rav's -
that "All that is prohibited for appearance's sake is also forbidden when
done privately" - is dealt with in the Bavli. The principle, similarly
attributed to Rav and similarly confronted with similar versions of the same
tannaitic sources, is cited and discussed by the Bavli on four separate
occasions[61]. Where the Yerushalmi permits itself to
dismiss as groundless the tannaitic rulings that contradict Rav, the Bavli
manages to retain them, never to overstep the conservative limits of a strictly
traditionalist discursive framework, and yet to achieve the very same. In all
four cases, just as in Berakhot 19b, the tannaitic texts are
reinterpreted so as to comply with Rav's view. The Bavli's rhetoric here is so
different from that of the Yerushalmi that it does not even seen fit to employ
the meitivi format. Thus in
Bavli, Avoda Zara 12a, to take but one example, the mention of Rav's
principle is initially prompted by a beraita that is concerned with
prohibitions for appearances' sake per se.
Our Rabbis taught: It is forbidden to enter
a city in which idolatrous worship is taking place therein, or to go from there
to another city; this is the opinion of R. Meir. But the Sages say, only when
the road leads solely to that city is it forbidden; if, however, the road does
not lead exclusively to that place, it is permitted[62].
Both
parties hence agree that it is forbidden to appear as if one is on one's way to
participate, or from participating in idolatrous worship. R. Meir adopts a
stricter view than the Sages in cases where there is more than one plausible
interpretation of a person's behavior. But all agree on the principle of the
matter. The question of whether or not actions forbidden for appearances' sake
are allowed when performed privately is not raised by the beraita, nor
do the dispute and ruling recorded by it bear on the question in any way. As
for the issue of prohibition due to appearances, the Bavli goes on to cite
three additional tannaitic rulings. And it is here that Rav's views on the
matter appear to be contradicted.
If a splinter has got into his foot while in
front of an idol, he should not bend down to extract it, because he may appear
as bowing to the idol; but if he is not seen[63] it is permitted.
If his coins got scattered in front of an idol he should not bend to retrieve them, for he may be taken as bowing to the idol; but if he is not seen it is permitted.
If there is a spring flowing in front of an
idol he should not bend down and drink, because he may appear to be bowing to
the idol; but if he is not seen it is permitted.
Not surprisingly, Rav's
principle makes its appearance in the sugya apropos the second,
qualifying clause of the beraitot, in which permission is granted if and
when one is "not seen". "What is meant by 'not being
seen'?" asks the s'tam,
Shall we say (that it means) that he is not
being observed? Surely (not, because) R. Yehuda stated in the name of Rav that
whatever the Sages prohibited for appearances' sake is also forbidden in one's
innermost chambers! It can only mean that it is permitted if (by bending) he
does not seem to be bowing to the idol.
The Bavli's response to the
seeming contradiction between the three beraitot and Rav's ruling, is
not to declare any of the sources involved invalid, but, as in Berakhot
19b, to harmonize all by reinterpreting the three tannaitic ones. What they really
mean, explains the s'tam, is that a person standing in the vicinity of
an idol is permitted to retrieve his fallen coins, kneel to drink, etc., not
when his actions happens to go unobserved, but only when he is able to do so
without appearing to be bowing! This feat of harmonization is achieved without
the Bavli having to declare Rav's ruling even prima facie problematic.
The meitivi format is not employed because the tannaitic sources - as
the Bavli quotes them - require very little interpretive effort in order to
cohere with Rav's latter-day position.
Significantly,
the original Tosefta includes two rather than one qualifying clause. It
is prohibited to appear as if one is bowing to an idol, "but",
continues the Tosefta, "if he should crouch down (to retrieve his coins or
drink) with his back turned (to the idol), or if he is in a place where
he is not seen, it is permitted". Indeed the Tosefta permits one to stoop
in the presence of an idol in two separate cases: if one does so without
seeming to be bowing, or if one does so without being seen to
bow. Focusing exclusively on Rav's edict, the Yerushalmi, understandably only
cites the latter[64] and is therefore forced to make a choice.
The Bavli, on the other hand, avoids the confrontation entirely by running
together the Tosefta's two qualifications[65], and pooh-poohing the very suggestion that
Rav might have defied a bona fide, uncontested tannaitic ruling. But by
sounding less radical the Bavli does not achieve less that the
Yerushalmi. As in Berakhot, here too Rav's view is retained lock, stock
and barrel, the seemingly discordant tannaitic sources are rendered inoffensive
by a stroke of creative interpretative reformulation, and, once more, a
significant halakhic revision is achieved without the Bavli having to sound
as if it is.
4. Antitraditionalism for the Advanced
Such
is the framers of the Bavli's way of negotiating across the great
amoraic-tannaitic divide: free, as any antitraditionalist would be, to align
themselves with whichever position they see fit, yet, at the same time,
careful, very careful to harmonize the texts involved whenever ruling in favor
of the latter-day position. In this sense Bavli, Berakhot 19b is
absolutely typical. What makes it in my opinion also absolutely unique is the
way in which a lesson appears to have been made out of it. In Berakhot 19b
the framer of the sugya is engaged in more than the negotiation of yet
another meitivi confrontation. Here, as nowhere else I know, I suggest
that the s'tam has chosen inaudibly to address his better-versed
readerships in order to all but outwardly declare his antitraditionalism, but
to do so without ever missing a beat of his carefully crafted traditionalist
way of speaking. I would even suggest further, that it is here perhaps that the
framers of the Bavli also make their stand in what appears to have been a
significant disagreement with their Palestinian counterparts about the
appropriate ways of conveying and passing down their shared vision of talmud-Torah.
If
one is willing to entertain the possibility - as a provisional working
hypothesis, for which, however, to the best of my knowledge there exists no
independent evidence - that the framer of this particular sugya was
writing with some knowledge of the Yerushalmi's treatment of at least some of
the relevant material, then it is even less plausible that he was engaged in a
straightforward traditionalist exercise. Thus for example, had he been seeking
for no more than to ward off alleged tannaitic challenges to Rav's ruling, it
would have made much better sense for him, for instance, to have cited the
Yerushalmi's version of R. Zeira's dictum than the one he does. The version
attributed to R. Zeira speaks sufficiently vaguely of consideration for human
dignity overriding "negative precept[s]" without actually saying
"of the Torah". In this manner it would have been much easier to
limit it, as the Bavli labors hard to argue, exclusively to rabbinic edicts.
But no. Defiantly, or so it seems, the s'tam confronts Rav's
affirmation, that care for the dignity of even one's own teacher is powerless
to override a transgression of God's word (name), with a tannaitic formulation
that prima facie could not have been more explicit in stating the very
opposite - so great are considerations of human dignity, the tanna asserts,
that it overrides the (all?) negative precepts of the Torah. Rather than
employ a less offensive version such as R. Zeira's - assuming, of course that
such a version was available to the Bavli redactor - or fall back on the
special license granted by the Bavli to Rav that allows him to contest
tannaitic opinion, the s'tam chooses to challenge us, his readers, with
a bold, almost reckless, display of hermeneutic freedom. 'Look how far one can
go', he seems to exclaim, 'see how much can be achieved without appearing to
violate the polite traditionalist rules of transgenerational discourse'. 'Even
as we speak', he seems to whisper inaudibly to all those capable or willing to
hear, 'most of my readers remain quite oblivious to what we are really up to'.
So far-fetched is Rav b. Shaba's rendition of the beraita, that the s'tam,
fully aware of how far he has allowed himself to go, has the members of that
academy of old snigger along with the most attentive of his present-day
students.
Intriguing
as it may seem, and plausible as it might sound, the idea that the Bavli's
engagement with its tannaitic heritage was even partly conducted in willful
disagreement with that of the Yerushalmi, is one for which the present author
lacks both the knowledge and training to seriously pursue. The differences in style,
temperament and idiom between the ways in which the transgenerational divide is
negotiated by the two talmudim speak for themselves, and, in my opinion,
are worthy of further study. And they are certainly relevant to the task of
laying bare the Bavli's treatment of meitivi-type confrontations in
general. But in order to appreciate the uniqueness of Berakhot 19b one
need not even be aware of the Yerushalmi's different way of doing things, or,
if aware, need not necessarily agree with my account of the Yerushalmi, let
alone assume that the Bavli was consciously reacting to it. Whether or not the sugya
in hand was intended to score points in a wider, second-order debate with the s'tam's
former Palestinian counterparts is irrelevant to assessing my claim that this
particular set of transgenerational confrontations was (also?) constructed with
a view to giving away the Bavli's game to its better-trained readers. The
evidence for this is, as it should be, wholly internal.
As
we have seen, although Rav's ruling is keenly confronted with five different,
seemingly contradicting tannaitic sources, the framer of the sugya does
much to suggest, though without actually saying so, that it is also
contradicted by the Mishna under discussion and the beraita apropos of
which it was quoted. The Gemara more than insinuates, but nowhere states openly
that it understands the exemptions from major religious duties granted by the
Mishna and beraita are due to considerations of human dignity – in which
case, the better-versed reader gradually realizes, they too are in worrying
violation of Rav's later ruling. Once it is noticed that the Mishna and beraita
should have also been confronted with Rav, the confrontations that are
considered and resolved only add to the confusion. This is because the ways in
which they are resolved are irrelevant to the Mishna and beraita;
neither of which can be said to involve transgressions of only rabbinic edicts.
The increasingly felt tension between the three texts, lingering unmentioned
and unresolved in the background, serves, deliberately in my opinion, to
invalidate the air of harmony created by the meitivi confrontations that
are negotiated.
It
is difficult to explain to someone who has not studied the Bavli closely just
how odd this is. It is highly uncommon for the Gemara to miss or overlook such
a clear discrepancy between a text that it has deliberately introduced and is
closely scrutinizing and the very Mishna under consideration - especially if
the text is attributed to an amora! Had the Mishna (or the beraita)
explicitly mentioned the notions of respect or dignity, such an oversight would
have been inconceivable. On the other hand, the closer one studies the sugya
it appears less and less conceivable that the Gemara could have understood the
Mishna's ruling as motivated by anything but considerations of respect
and human dignity! Given the specific rulings of the Mishna and beraita,
what was the point of citing Rav's edict in the first place, if not to confront
the three texts? and yet their mutual incongruity is passed over in incredible
silence. Perhaps, one inevitably finds oneself asking, there are texts, such as
the five mentioned, that can be somehow squared with Rav's views, but there are
others, among them clearly the Mishna itself, that, by the end of the day,
remain in opposition to Rav despite their obvious priority? In which case
perhaps the name of the game is not, as the Bavli normally has us believe,
harmony at all costs? Perhaps, regardless of the way the five meitivi
queries were resolved, Rav and other leading amoraic authorities are not
strictly required to follow in the footsteps of their predecessors in all
matters? Perhaps the halakha admits not only to innovation, but also to
revolution? Perhaps the Bavli's rhetoric of transgenerational harmony is merely
rhetoric? In the very act of harmonizing away meitivi-type objections in
the normal manner, the s'tam seems to be indicating, quite strongly,
that he shouldn't be taken seriously. Rav's move is revolutionary, he
all but says out loud, for it knowingly contradicts the entire tannaitic
tradition represented by the Mishna and Tosefta, and if the harmonization of
the other five texts seems to you affected and strained, well, you are quite
right!
The
second unusual feature of the meitivi confrontations of Berakhot
19b is the absolutely unique manner in which they are introduced. As noted
previously, nowhere else in the Bavli does a meitivi-type objection come
accompanied by a running commentary in which the s’tam explains which of
the two texts he finds puzzling, and why. meitivi-type confrontations
are elsewhere always introduced by the exact same format:
amora A says X;
"meitivi": tannaitic authority (B) implies the negation
of X.
The s'tam's only
"original" contribution of his own at this stage (apart from
juxtaposing the two sources) is the word "meitivi" itself.
Given their obvious incongruity, the problem it constitutes is apparently
considered to be self explanatory.
Self-evident
or not, what the problem is, however, will crucially depend on the point
of view of whoever raises it. For a dedicated traditionalist the difficulty
generated by a transgenerational incongruity will always be one and the same:
how was it possible for amora A to say X if an authoritative tannaitic
source appears to imply not-X? In order to merit inclusion within the
system of halakha latter-day rulings must be shown (a) to fully cohere with all
former rulings, and (b) to legislate for cases, situations or circumstances for
which no former ruling is known to apply. In the event of an apparent
transgenerational incongruity, it will always be the amoraic ruling that comes
as a surprise, never be the tannaitic source.
But
if one's meta-halakhic point of departure is antitraditionalist, such texts are
allowed to contradict one another, and, in a truly antitraditionalist world of
discourse, they frequently will. Antitraditionalists allow for halakhic change,
and view halakhic development in revisionary, rather than cumulatory terms.
Antitraditionalist also require of the mandatory halakhic system that it be at
all times consistent, but they do not require that the demand for
consistency extend to all authoritative rulings ever made. For the prudent
antitraditionalist, casting about for transgenerational contradictions is more
a form of bookkeeping, a check-listing of which rulings are in and which are
out, that normally privileges the more recent. But even the most avid
antitraditionalists will never advocate halakhic change for the sake of sheer
novelty. Antitraditionalists are more than willing to accept halakhic reform,
even halakhic revolution, but they have to have good reasons for doing so. It
follows, therefore, that when an antitraditionalist presents a
transgenerational inconsistency between two rulings as a problem, the
ruling he will be challenging will be the one for which he sees relatively less
reason regardless of its formal priority.
If
asked to fully spell out their questions, traditionalists and
antitraditionalists will elaborate very differently on meitivi-type
confrontations. For the former, to repeat, the question will always reduce to:
how was it possible for amora A to say X if an authoritative
tannaitic source appears to imply the exact opposite? Since it was obviously possible
for this to happen, a slightly more sophisticated traditionalist formulation of
the question would be: because it is unthinkable for amora A to have
knowingly contradicted the tannaitic source in hand, we must assume that he had
read it differently - if so, how? Since a traditionalist’s obligation to bona
fide tannaitic rulings is unconditional, he will never seriously question the
tannaitic sources motives for stating what it states.
None of this
applies to the antitraditionalist. The only real difficulties an
antitraditionalist would encounter in the course of a meitivi-type
confrontation, would be to do with motives and reasons. And since for him
latter-day positions are expected to be outcomes of serious trouble-shooting of
earlier ones, it is only natural that the earlier, tannaitic source will
frequently turn out to be the more puzzling of the two. If asked to spell out
the difficulty perceived in a meitivi-type confrontation, an
antitraditionalist will, therefore, most probably describe it thus: amora A
claims that the halakha should be X for reason R. Curiously, the
tannaitic text in hand implies the negation of X. Why, as seems to be
the case, did the tannaitic authors not think of R or deem R
inappropriate? Only an avid antitraditionalist will be able to seriously
formulate a meitivi-type query in this fashion. And this is precisely
the way the framer of Berakhot 19b scrupulously describes the puzzlement
entailed by each of the five meitivi-type confrontations he conducts. Of each
of the five beraitot he asks the same: "Why (is this so)?" Why
doesn't the beraita say as does Rav that "There is no wisdom nor
understanding nor counsel against the Lord" (and hence: wherever a
profanation of God's name is involved no respect is paid (even) to a
teacher)"? Unless we interpret the s'tam's formula as a rhetorical,
somewhat sarcastic challenge to Rav - a reading I find highly inappropriate -
It is hard not to read it as a clear, if fleeting revealing of
antitraditionalist bias.
In
addition to the clear antitraditionalist gist and content of the s'tam's
comments, it is the insistent, case-by-case, chant-like repetition of identical
interrogative formulae that serves to create the distinct impression of a
schoolroom example I spoke of above. If one studies Berakhot 19b
attentively, with some knowledge of similar sugyot, one has the distinct
feeling of being patiently, very patiently taught to what a meitivi
objection amounts, and how to pose it. The lesson, however, is completely lost
on two kinds of reader: the less knowledgeable students who simply fail to
register both the uniqueness and significance of the s'tam's explicatory
remarks, and the quicker, better informed readers who, perhaps because of their
former experience with meitivi-type queries, no longer bother to pause
and think between question and answer despite the s'tam's patient
prompting. Reluctant to give the game away too obviously, or so it seems, the s'tam
does not allow the antitraditionalism of his didactic interventions to linger
long enough to really sink in. Although the problems generated by each of the beraitot
are explicated as only an antitraditionalist could describe them, they are
each immediately resolved, or rather harmonized out of existence, in ways only
a dedicated traditionalist would deem fit. In other words, with regard to
the meitivi confrontations themselves, the framer of Berakhot 19b
flashes his antitraditionalism repeatedly, but each time only for the briefest
of moments between posing the question and proposing an answer, never long
enough for it to have a real effect. By the time each of the questions has been
answered, all trace of whatever antitraditionalism was allowed to briefly make
its appearance in the course of presenting them, has been effectively
obliterated.
Indeed,
had the unusual formulation of the five questions been my only evidence, my
case would have been exceedingly unconvincing, if not downright silly. But it
is not. There is much more to the sugya than meets the eye. We have already
seen how Rav's ruling remains conspicuously unharmonized with both the
Mishna and Tosefta. If it would be out of character for a traditionalist
seriously to entertain the thought that, or wonder in all seriousness why, a
tannaitic authority had failed to employ a line of reasoning successfully
applied by an amora, it would be downright unthinkable for a traditionalist
construction of a sugya such as this to leave two such major
transgenerational contradictions untreated. On the other hand, the way the sugya
responds to the five questions, nicely corroborates such a reading. From an
antitraditionalist perspective, however, the exact opposite is true. It is
equally unthinkable that a hard-nosed antitraditionalist would invest such
effort in harmonizing away the five transgenerational incongruities. On the
other hand, the unresolved tension between Rav's ruling and the two tannaitic
texts, not to say the non-ironic expression of puzzlement regarding the
motivation for the rulings registered in the beraitot, would be the
natural response for a narrator writing from an unabashed
antitraditionalist perspective.
The
situation is not symmetrical, however. The assumptions that a traditionalist or
an antitraditionalist could have framed the sugya are not equally
improbable. Only the former option is genuinely inconceivable. The only way the
sugya could be attributed to a prudent traditionalist is by writing off
his failure to attend to the inconsistency between Rav's ruling and the two
tannaitic sources as an incredible oversight, and by reading his declaration of
surprise at the five tannaitic rulings as expressions of sarcasm addressed to
Rav - both of which seem so out of character as to count as almost conclusive
grounds for rejecting them. By contrast, all one needs to assume in order to
sustain an antitraditionalist rendition of the sugya, is that the
harmonization of the five beraitot with Rav's later ruling is not
performed with utmost seriousness; that the sugya is contrived in this
respect ironically to lay bare the hollowness and sheer formality of the
Bavli's feigned traditionalism in this type of confrontation. From an
antitraditionalist perspective, the sugya under consideration is a
masterly crafted attempt subtly to expose, to a small and select
readership, the policy and program that ground an entire class of similar units
of talmudic discourse. By contrast, those who prefer to take the traditionalist
format literally, are forced to explain the sugya, ad hoc, as a fantastic case
of careless editing. But even that is not the whole story. Two additional
features of this remarkable sugya serve, in my opinion, to tip the
balance decisively in favor of the antitraditionalist option. The first
concerns the passage preceding, and leading up to the discussion of Rav's
ruling, the second concerns the passage immediately succeeding it.
5. Giving away the Game, or The Gentle Art of Inaudible
Instruction
Rav's
dictum that "wherever a profanation of God's name is involved no respect
is paid (even) to a teacher" is not the first mention of respect for
teachers, kevod la-rav or kevod ha-rav, that occurs in the sugya.
The issue is raised a page earlier in a relatively long and rather strange
discussion of a claim made by another first generation amora, R. Yehoshua b.
Levi who is quoted as claiming that "In twenty-four places (it is taught
that) the bet din excommunicates a person for (reasons to do with)
respect to a teacher - and we learn them all in our Mishna". Despite its
vague phrasing, all commentators without exception take R. Yehoshua b. Levi to
be claiming that, as Rashi puts it, on twenty-four occasions the Sages are
reported by the Mishna to have excommunicated individuals for acting
disrespectfully towards their teachers. The matter, however, may not be as
simple as it sounds. In all, five incidents of rabbinic excommunication are
cited. The fact that none of the cases mentioned seem to have anything to do
with disrespect for teachers is puzzling in itself. But the strangest, and in
my opinion, the most interesting aspect of the discussion, is the fact that at
least two of the cases cited imply the exact opposite - namely, that
individuals were excommunicated by Sages for being too respectful of
their teachers! Alongside the actual excommunication of one Elazar b. Hanokh
- for opposing the ritual washing of hands decreed by the rabbis - and would-be
banning of Honi ha-Ma'agel and Todos of Rome - the former for the
petulant manner of his pleading with the Almighty, and the latter for
permitting his community to eat on Passover a kid roasted in a way that
resembled too closely the Temple ritual - we find mentioned the two great
antitraditionalist tannaitic legends of excommunication I discuss in earlier
chapters of the book[66] - that of Akavia b. Mehalal'el and that of R. Eliezer b.
Hyrqanus[67]. Neither of which is told in any detail.
They are briefly alluded to, assuming, so it seems, that the reader is
well-acquainted with the material.
As
in the discussion of Rav's principle that follows almost immediately, here too,
I shall argue, one encounters a surface impression that not only contradicts a
more sophisticated reading of the text, but seems to have been deliberately
constructed in order to conceal it. To begin at the most explicit and seemingly
obvious level. What we appear to be told by R. Yehoshua b. Levi is of a firm,
and uncontested tannaitic tradition, widely attested to by the Mishna, that so
valorizes the honor and respect due to teachers as to deem those who fail in
this respect liable to be banned. The discussion that follows seeks to
corroborate both of R. Yehoshua b. Levi's claims: (a) that such a tannaitic
tradition exists, and (b) that evidence for it is found not only in beraitot,
but also in the Mishna itself. Still keeping to initial, superficial
impressions, the discussion seems to yield whatever it was intended to yield.
The details, at this level of reading, are unimportant. What matters is that
(a) and (b) are not outwardly disputed, and Mishnaic evidence of such a policy
seems to produced to the s'tam's satisfaction. The only aspect of R.
Yehoshua b. Levi's claim that is contested is the number of relevant examples
to be found in the Mishna. Rather than twenty-four these turn out to be only
three, or at most not to exceed five. But that is beside the point. The idea that
the Mishna maintains that disrespectful behavior toward a teacher is
sufficient reason for excommunication goes unchallenged, and by implication,
undisputed. Less than a page later, Rav will, of course, claim that the value
laid on the respect due even to one's teachers is nevertheless outranked by the
value laid on fully and promptly carrying out one's religious duties. At the
cursory level of having to treat one's mentors politely the two claims
jar somewhat, but do not contradict each other. One stresses the value of
respecting one's Master while the other explicates its limits. But in talmudic
culture, kevod ha-rav means more than courtesy.
In
talmudic culture, the very term 'respect for teachers' refers first and
foremost to respect for their teachings. A disciple who issues an edict
or even pronounces a particular low-level ruling in the vicinity of his still
functioning Master, we are told in several places - not surprisingly perhaps,
always apropos a story about the arch-traditionalist R. Eliezer b. Hyrqanus -
is punishable by death, even if his ruling coincides with his master's opinion
and is perfectly correct[68]. To openly disagree with one's
teacher is even worse. "To dispute one's teacher" says R. Hisda,
"is like disputing the Almighty", to which R. Hanina b. R.
Papa adds: "To even think of doing so, is as if one was thinking of
contesting the Almighty[69]." All this is not as blatantly
traditionalist as it sounds. Once a person ends his studentship, we are told
elsewhere, and becomes a talmid-haver - a recognized fellow
academician in his own right - he is no longer expected to follow his former
Master to the letter, or to belittle himself to such an extent in his presence[70]. Still, when applied to the special realm
of kevod ha-rav, the realm of a person's duties regarding the teachings
of his master, the incongruity between the position attributed by R. Yehoshua
b. Levi to the Mishna and that attributed to Rav becomes far more pronounced.
Bearing this connotation of kevod ha-rav in mind, Rav's ruling acquires
an additional and new aspect: if one is convinced that a profanation of God's
name is in the making, Rav's principle now implies, one is expected no longer
to pay respect to one's teacher's teachings. While R. Yehoshua b. Levi
appears to be claiming in the name of the Mishna that those who contradict
their mentors are liable to be excommunicated, when dully generalized Rav's
principle implies that if one truly believes his masters to be wrong, and
liable, as a result, to cause a "profanation of God's name", one is required
to set aside all considerations of honor and respect, and to speak one's mind.
Interestingly, elsewhere in the Bavli Rav's ruling is explicitly employed to
mean just that[71].
Read
thus, Rav's principle is rendered more than the mere outcome of a covert
antitraditionalist move; more than a curiously veiled, surreptitious halakhic
breaking with the past. It now reads, also, or perhaps even mainly, as an all
but open declaration of antitraditionalism itself! Not only is one
obliged to publicly strip if thought to be wearing mixed kinds even in the
presence of one's teacher, but, Rav now seems strongly to suggest, one is
required outwardly to contest one's teacher's teachings and rulings if they are
genuinely thought to be inappropriate. The implication is that just as one is
encouraged constantly to check all garments for mixed kinds with a view to
taking action whenever thought necessary, one is likewise encouraged critically
to scrutinize everything one learns with a view similarly to speaking one's
mind whenever thought necessary - even in public, even to the embarrassment of
one’s teachers. Even great teachers are fallible and capable, therefore, in both
their conduct and their teaching, of unwittingly causing the Divine Name to be profaned.
And if teachers are believed to be fallible, so are their students. Hence,
individuals taking action on the grounds of Rav's principle should willy-nilly
regard their own views and decisions to act, equally liable to be mistaken, and
should, therefore act cautiously, keep an open mind, and be willing to hear
whatever criticism comes their way. It is most significant, in my opinion, that
closely following the discussion of Rav's principle the s'tam presents
the story of R. Ada b. Ahava who mistook a heathen for an Israelite and tore
from her head an improper headgear, only to be humbled by a high fine of
four-hundred Zuzim[72].
In
short, if Rav's principle can be said to sustain such a reading - and Bavli, Eruvin
63a apparently presumes that it does[73] - then it clearly implies, if not actually
proclaims all the main elements of antitraditionalism. Needless to say,
according to R. Yehoshua b. Levi "our Mishna" appears to suggest the
opposite. If one is in real danger of excommunication, who would never even
consider publicly stripping or contradicting a teacher! Viewed thus, the Mishna
implies that society cannot tolerate challenges to the authority of its
teachers. Taking the place of a teacher, let alone actually defying his
teachings, even for the best of causes may result in untimely death by the
hands of Heaven and/or banishment by the hands of the courts. Regarding one’s
master’s teachings – as opposed to his attire or conduct - the implications are
centrally traditionalist. At the most superficial level, then, before studying
the discussion of R. Yehoshua b. Levi's claim in depth, the passage devoted to
it by the s'tam would seem to give rise to yet another set of tensions
between the ruling attributed to Rav and the alleged policies of the Mishna. While
Rav's words are confronted with a series of seemingly contradicting beraitot,
and the apparent contradiction between his ruling and the specific ruling of
the Mishna in relation to which it is cited hovers seemingly unperceived in the
background, the s'tam appears to be doing his best to prove that the
Mishna, in particular and as a whole, beraitot not with standing[74], is not party to the antitraditionalism
suggested by Rav's principle. Here, though, the tension is no longer contained
within the tolerable limits of a specific incongruity between specific halakhic
rulings. If until now Rav's ruling had seemed at most to be in disagreement
with the particular edict recorded in the particular Mishna under
consideration, he now is seen to be contesting the Mishna's general
metahalakhic, second-order principle according to which such discordancy is
itself improper!
The
way in which a cursory reading of one passage seems to amplify a considerably
deeper understanding of the one that follows is interesting, perhaps even
elegant, but it is also slightly worrying. It is worrying because by presenting
the antitraditionalism residing in Rav's principle and surreptitiously revealed
in the meitivi-type confrontations it undergoes, as opposed to
the Mishna's general outlook, the s'tam's position is debilitated rather
than bolstered. If, as I suspect, the framer of the sugya contrives
quietly to draw attention to the extent of his own antitraditionalist
commitment, it is hard to imagine what he intended to achieve by citing and
discussing the words of R. Yehoshua b. Levi simpliciter. If indeed this
was his intention, it would have been far more effective for him to raise and
discuss a less obviously traditionalist pronouncement of the Mishna's point of
view.
But
then why should we compare a superficial reading of one unit of discourse with
a far more subtle and deeper reading of the one that follows it? It makes far
more sense to maintain a even level of reading for both passages. Read
superficially, the meitivi discussion of Rav's principle, I have argued
all along, is as traditionalist as they come. The entire discussion is geared
on such a showing to prove that Rav's ruling conveyed absolutely nothing new -
or so it seems. At such a cursory level of reading it is almost certain that
the tension between Rav's ruling and the Mishna would also go unnoticed. At
this level of reading, then, the two passages mesh nicely - with the
traditionalism implied by R. Yehoshua b. Levi's claim effectively grounding
that of the blissful harmony allegedly sought and found between the ruling of
his amoraic colleague and the entire tannaitic tradition that went before it. A
closer look, however, not only changes our perception of the discussion of Rav
completely as we have seen, but also that of R. Yehoshua b. Levi.
In
its discussion of R. Yehoshua b. Levi's assertion the Gemara cites five
examples of actual and would-be bans issued by tannaitic authorities, of which,
it claims, only four are mentioned in the Mishna itself. The claim is true. The
excommunications of Akavia b. Mehalal'el and Elazar b. Hanokh are
related in Mishna, Eduyot 5:6-7, the threat to excommunicate Honi
ha-Ma'agel is noted in Mishna, Ta'anit 3:8, and the dispute associated
with the banishment of R. Eliezer b. Hyrqanus is mentioned in Mishna, Kelim
5:10 and Eduyot 7:7. On the other hand, the threat we find in Tosefta Beitza
2:15, to banish Todos of Rome for permitting his congregation to eat kids
roasted in their entirety on Passover, is nowhere mentioned in the Mishna.
Despite this, I believe this fifth case, unmentioned by the Mishna, may be a
key to the entire passage.
Although
the threat to Todos is not noted by the Mishna, the issue of eating this type
of roasted kid on Passover is mentioned twice. Both Mishna, Beitza 2:7
and Eduyot 3:11 report that Raban Gamliel held to the view that kids
prepared in this fashion can be eaten outside the Temple on Passover night.
His, we are told, was a minority opinion, however, that was voted down by a
majority of his Jabne colleagues. As far as the Mishna is concerned - and the
question in point is the Mishna's view on these matters - there was
nothing prima facie wrong in Raban Gamliel believing that a full
roast be permitted on Passover, or in his announcing his belief, or in his
arguing the case with his colleagues. The Mishna does not give the Sages'
reasons for voting against Raban Gamliel's proposal, but we may assume,
following the Tosefta's remarks with regard to Todos, that the issue at stake
was probably a desire not to emulate the Temple rituals too closely outside the
Temple Compound. The point is that Raban Gamliel is not reprimanded for
adopting the more liberal approach, but, as is commonplace in any Great Bet
Din or bet midrash, is merely voted down. Todos, on the other hand,
is not reported to have merely opined that such a dish was permitted on
Passover, but to have issued a ruling to the effect. Because of this he was
threatened by excommunication. If dignity and respect can at all be said to be
involved here, it is respect for the current halakhic authority, the majority
of one's peers, and not that of one's present or former teachers. Had Raban
Gamliel refused to accept the ruling of his colleagues, we may safely assume
that he would have been called to task. And, as in the case of R. Eliezer b.
Hyrqanus or that of Akavia b. Mehalal'el, the opinions of his former teachers
would have had nothing to do with it!
This
I believe is the intended import of at least three of the four incidents found
by the Gemara to be of the Mishna itself. The case of Honi ha-Ma'agel is
the exception. His sin is that of "arrogance against the Most High",
as A. Cohen puts it[75]. The other three - Akavia, R. Eliezer and
Elazar b. Hanokh - were banished for arrogantly opposing, not the Almighty,
but the halakhic authorities of their day. The point is that the halakhic
authorities of their day were not their teachers or mentors, but the
majority of their colleagues! Those acquainted with the original stories
well know that the banishing of Akavia and R. Eliezer was the result of them
having followed the received teachings of their masters too closely! How
could it be that the two most vividly antitraditionalist legends in the entire
talmudic corpus are recruited here as confirmation of the Mishna's alleged
traditionalism?! The answer, I have indicated (and flesh out further in the
book[76]), is that, again, the s'tam has
ingeniously constructed a sugya that speaks deliberately in two distinct
and disharmonious voices, addressed to two distinct readerships; two voices
that mesh remarkably well with the two equally discordant voices that, I have
suggested, typify the meitivi-discussion of Rav's principle that follows
closely in its wake. Talk of a tannaitic policy of banning for reasons of kevod
ha-rav, as we have seen, introduces the kind of formal, yet hollow
traditionalist superstructure, similar to the rhetoric of meitivi-confrontations,
through which those acquainted with the material can hardly fail to see. It is
precisely the type of self-refuting 'Doublespeak' that distinguishes the
advanced students from the beginners.
The
final point I wish to make regarding the antitraditionalist subtext of Berakhot
19b concerns the culmination of the sugya. Here there is no longer need
for subtlety or knowledge of other texts. For a brief moment, the s'tam
seems to throw all caution to the wind, and to announce his metahalakhic
preferences for all to hear. He does so in the form of a dialogue between R.
Papa and Abaye that constitutes one of the boldest amoraic statements of
antitraditionalism of which I am aware. The dialogue, I believe, speaks for
itself.
Asked R. Papa of Abaye: "In what were
our predecessors different from us that miracles occurred for them though for
us they do not? Could it be a question of learning? (Surely not.) In the days
of R. Yehuda (for example) all they learnt (knew) was (the Order of) Nezikin,
whereas we study (know) all six Orders -
(Indeed) when R. Yehuda used to reach (the mishna in) Uktzin[77] (concerning) "If a woman presses vegetables
in a pot"[78] - and some say (it was when he reached the
one concerning) "Olives pressed with their leaves are ritually clean"[79] - he would say 'I see here (a complexity of
the same order as) the disputations of (my teachers) Rav and Shmuel' (but was
unable to explain it himself). We (by contrast, are able to) study Uktzin
in thirteen different ways[80]. Yet R. Yehuda would only have to remove
one of his shoes for rain to begin to fall[81], while we can afflict our souls and cry and
cry and no one listens! He said to him: (it is not a matter of learning,
rather) our predecessors jeopardized their lives for the sanctification of the
Name, and we do not[82].
The previously noted story of R.
Ada b. Ahava's unfortunate mistake and four-hundred Zuzim fine is then
presented presumably as an example of how former Sages would risk all for the
sanctification of the Name, kiddush ha-shem.
On the one hand, R. Papa's statement conveys
far more than an antitraditionalist would ever need. In order to justify the
adoption of a critical attitude towards the knowledge and teachings of former
generations, it quite sufficient to assume that all humans are fallible, that
circumstances can change in ways that are liable to defy the most canny
foresight, that even if the quality of learning of later generations is less
than that of their predecessors they may still be considered dwarfs standing on
the shoulders of giants. More than it may be considered a justification of
antitraditionalism, R. Papa's bold assessment of the vast superiority of the
knowledge and learning of his own generation in comparison to that of R. Yehuda
constitutes a flat refutation of traditionalism. If it is true, it leaves no
room at all for the type of commitment to former learning necessarily premised
by traditionalism, and seemingly presupposed in the rhetoric of standard meitivi-type
confrontations.
On
the other hand, the s'tam still succeeds in remaining ambiguous with
regard to one crucial aspect. Forceful as it is, R. Papa's declaration is still
not enough to prevent a traditionalist rendition of meitivi-type
challenges completely, for the simple reason that he cautiously limits his
assessment to the amoraic period. Traditionalists can still claim - and I can
personally attest to the fact that many of them do! - that even if R. Papa and
Abaye were right about the standard of their amoraic predecessors, it is
unthinkable to even consider disputing a tannaitic ruling, let alone criticize
the quality of their learning. Those who failed to take note of the unnoted
incongruity between Rav's ruling and the Mishna and Tosefta, who passed by the s'tam's
tedious running commentary to the five meitivi confrontations, who
ignored the discrepancy between R. Yehoshua b. Levi b. Levi's generalization
and its alleged instances, will also, in all probability, read R. Papa's
exchange with Abaye for its moral conclusion rather than for its
epistemological premise. Despite the bold, and seemingly unequivocal message
conveyed by R. Papa's statement, the antithetical, two-tier meaning of the sugya
as a whole is retained to the very end.
As
I said at the outset, the significance of the meitivi confrontations of Berakhot
19b is enormous precisely because qua meitivi confrontations they are
wholly and totally typical. The five tannaitic challenges to Rav's ruling and
their subsequent resolutions are so commonplace that, when studied, they are
normally skimmed through with ease. They are not a parody of their kind in any
obvious sense. Even the sniggers earned by Rav b. Shaba's far-fetched attempt
to harmonize Rav's ruling with the tannaitic principle associated by the
Yerushalmi with R. Zeira, are not immediately taken by the reader as having
anything at all to do with the idea of transgenerational harmonizing per se.
The ways in which the five meitivi challenges are resolved by the s'tam
do not appear to ridicule such solutions. On the contrary, the force and
subtlety of the s'tam's ironical exposition of their real meaning owes
much to the fact that, of themselves, they are entirely credible and wholly
representative of the Bavli's vast stock of similar negotiations. This is why I
suggest that Berakhot 19b should be seen as a paradigm rather than a
parody; as an extraordinarily constructed sugya that contrives to
explain rather than satirize the class of meitivi-type,
transgenerational negotiations. Viewed thus, Berakhot 19b is seen as an
instructive, explanatory effort on behalf of one of the framers of the Bavli's
many other sugyot of its kind, rather than that of an antagonistic
critic. It is, I urge, the work of an antitraditionalist doing his best to explain
the Bavli's antitraditionalist project, rather that of an antitraditionalist
aspiring to ridicule a traditionalist one.
All of this, however, is ingenuously
concealed. There is little chance that innocent beginners will be deprived of
their innocence by studying Berakhot 19b in its immediate context, any
more than practiced, committed traditionalists are liable to be forced to
rethink their former commitments. The s'tam, as we have seen, has
skillfully provided the former with blinkers and the latter with a convenient
safety-net, in the form of a largely plausible, if somewhat disconnected,
surface rhetoric that serves intriguingly well to mask the accumulating
evidence of his own unmistakable antitraditionalism from the eyes of those who
should not, or those who can, but desire not to appreciate it. I doubt,
however, that he would have mindfully catered for the latter. When it comes to
the inheritance of former authoritative documents of the type to which the
Bavli and Yerushalmi are almost wholly devoted, traditionalists and
antitraditionalist are too bitterly opposed to be expected to write and edit
their works with a view considerately to accommodate their adversaries. The s'tam's
ambiguity cannot be attributed, in my opinion, to a desire to provide the
traditionalist with an honorable way out. The fact that in retrospect it is
seen to do so is beside the point. His ambiguous double-talk, I have suggested
all along, seems intentionally to be catering to the beginner rather than to
the opposition.
So much for Berakhot 19b. The more the convincing one finds my reading of this incredible sugya, the more pressing becomes the inevitable why-question – namely, why bother? What could the s’tam be hoping to be achieve by thus misguiding the novices? The final chapter of rational Rabbis proposes a rather elaborate explanation with which I am no longer completely happy. At the TR session in November I shall set forth a somewhat different, and possibly supplementary approach I have been working on since the publication of Rabbis. The paper, not yet published, is in Hebrew, and can be obtained (along with any other part of the book, or subsequent publications) by contacting me at fisch@post.tau.ac.il
Menachem Fisch
August, 2002
[1] The book makes no attempt to pinpoint the dispute historically and is, therefore, unconcerned with the authenticity of texts that later talmudic compilations present as tannaitic. Certain bona fide tannaitic texts bear clear witness to the dispute (e.g. Mishna, Sanhedrin 11:2 versus Tosefta, Sanhedrin 7:1 and Haggiga 2:9, and Mishna versus Tosefta, Eduyot 1), as do several others others, presented as tannaitic by the Bavli. On the way the latter are occasionally manipulated by the Bavli to serve this purpose, see Shlomo Naeh’s fascinating “Ase Libkha Hadrei Hadarim: Iyyun Nosaf be-Divrei Hazal al ha-Mahloket”, in A Sagi and Z Zohar (eds.), Renewing Jewish Commitment: The Work and Thought of David Hartman, Hakibbutz Hameuchad, Tel Aviv 2001, vol II, pp. 851-75.
[2] Tosefta, Sanhedrin 7:1puts it: the entire system is governed by the principle that im sham’u, amru lahem – namely, that in all cases for which a halakhic tradition exists, the court - even the High Court, the Great Sanhedrin situated in the Hall of Hewn Stones - is obliged to rule accordingly. See also Tosefta, Haggiga 2:9.
[3] H. Shapira and M. Fisch, “Pulmusei ha-Batim: ha-Mahloket ha-Meta-Hilkhatit bein Bet Hillel u-Bet Shammai”, Iyyunei Mishpat, 22 (3), pp. 461-497, 1998
[4] In what follows I shall often use the term "Gemara" as shorthand for "the anonymous latter-day framer and narrator of the passage under consideration", who shall also be referred to interchangeably as "the s'tam" (the unnamed redactor) or "the framer of the sugya".
[5] The idea that an amora will never contradict a tanna - except when relying on a different tannaitic source - was first proposed as a general rule of talmudic scholarship in the tenth-century Iggeret Rav Sherira Gaon (ed. B.M. Levin, Haifa, 1921), p. 30. The Bavli and Yerushalmi themselves, however, contain no general statement to this effect. What the Bavli does offer (though not the Yerushalmi) are a number of specific comments that appear to premise the idea that an amora cannot formally and directly dispute an undisputed tannaitic ruling. On five occasions in which an opinion attributed to Rav is perceived to contradict views stated explicitly by the Mishna, the Gemara explains that since Rav is considered a tanna, he may challenge a mishna (Rav tanna u-palig). And on one occasion the same is said of R. Hiya. (For Rav, see: Bavli, Eruvin 50b; Ketubot 8a; Gitin 38b; Bava Batra 42a; Sanhedrin 83b. For R. Hiya: Bava Metzia 5a.) Elsewhere, however, when R. Yohanan, who is nowhere granted tannaitic status by the talmud, is found to have been in clear disagreement with an explicit beraita, Abaye suggests that he was probably not aware of its existence, and that had he been, he would have surely changed his mind. To this the anonymous narrator adds: "but then he might still have heard it and decided that the halakha should be different". (Bavli, Shabbat 61a. See also Bavli, Yoma 43b.)
[6] Strictly speaking, the 'great divide' established by the Bavli between the tannaitic and amoraic periods is somewhat artificial from the point of view of the avid traditionalist, who is equally committed to the reliably transmitted teachings of all preceding generations. To a significant degree the Bavli treats all generations of tannaim and all generations of amoraim as two extended peer-groups, members of which are 'permitted' as it were to criticize one another freely. There is seldom a problem for a fifth-generation amora, for instance, to criticize and contradict a second generation amora. There is nothing particularly antitraditionalist, however, about this curious fact. The great generational changing of the guard is experienced in and by the Bavli across the one dividing line between the two great texts it comprises: the Mishna and Gemara. The Bavli is about the reception of the Mishna by later generations. And it is in relation to this one crucial 'moment' that its philosophy of reception, interpretation and amelioration of prior texts is presented. One might say that more than the Bavli is a study of the relationship between consecutive generations of Torah learners, it is a study of the relationship between consecutive compositions by Torah-learners.
[7] If the amoraic statement is challenged with more than one tannaitic document, only the first of them will usually be introduced by meitivi or eitivei, while successive incongruous beraitot are presented by "ta shema" (come and hear) or t'nan (we have learnt). The main difference between objections introduced by meitivi and eitivei is that the latter describe a move in a narrated dialogue between named parties. We are told by the anonymous narrator that amora A responded to the ruling attributed to amora B by citing the following tannaitic source. In such cases, the understandings and policies regarding transgenerational incongruities may not necessarily reflect those of the narrator, who may very well be faithfully citing a dispute he himself had nothing to do with. By contrast, objections introduced by "meitivi" seldom aspire to describe moves performed in face-to-face dialogue at all. Here it is far more obvious that we are being addressed by the framer of the exchange, who is not merely reporting that someone or other considered the following to be an objection, but that he himself regards it as such. It is natural therefore, that a study such as the present one, in which the epistemological presuppositions of the framers of the Talmud are its main concern, will concentrate primarily on transgenerational confrontations of the meitivi, rather than the eitivei variety.
[8] This number does not include follow-up challenges to the same statements introduced by ta shema or t'nan. For convenience as well as for reasons outlined in the previous ftn., I shall refer to all such transgenerational objections as meitivi-type challenges, confrontations or objections.
[9] Not every double tyuvta is fatal. See Bavli, Berakhot 23b and Eruvin 16b where double tyuvtot are declared on positions proposed by Shmuel and R. Papa respectively, while at the same time ruling in their favor!
[10] Which is not to say that tannaitic sources are never discarded. On the contrary, the Bavli boasts an impressive array of editorial procedures by which it modifies, or declares corrupt tannaitic halakhic sources. These are employed, however, exclusively in the face of internal difficulties, never merely as a result of an amora thinking differently. For a detailed study of five such procedures see M. J. Yeres, “Studies in the Talmudic Emendation of Tannaitic Sources: An Analysis of Five Terms of Emendation in the Babylonian Talmud”, Doctoral Dissertation, Yeshiva University NY, 1987
[11] That is to say, has not yet been buried.
[12] To comfort the mourners.
[13] If they stand two or more deep.
[14] The main source for this principle, attributed to R. Yossi the Galilean, is a beraita cited in Bavli, Suka 26a whose formulation is strikingly similar to the Mishna under consideration here. Rashi, for one, appeals to this principle, with regard to the exemption granted to the mourner himself (Bavli, Berakhot 18a, V. "exempt from the recital of the shema"). The Tosafot, however, disagree (loc. cit. 17b, V "And he does not recite the blessing"). According to the Tosafot the principle at play is respect for the dead. The point of contention between them is the following: if the reason for the exemption is respect for the deceased, then one is not merely exempt from the other duties, but is actually forbidden to perform them even if he manages to find time to do so. If, however, the reason for the exemption is the mourner's engagement in other duties, he should be allowed to perform both if he is able to. The parallel passages in both Yerushalmi, Berakhot iii 5d and Minor Tractate, Semahot 10 (see next ftn.) appear to confirm the Tosafot's position.
[15] Minor Tractate, Semahot 10 opens similarly to the Mishna here: "For as long as his dead (relative) lies before him, a mourner is exempt from the recital of the shema and from the tefilla and from all the precepts mentioned in the Torah", but adds that if the mourner wishes to ignore the exemption and recite the shema anyway, he should not "out of respect for the dead". Indeed, the Mishna continues, When the time for the recital of the shema arrives, the entire congregation recites (it) and he remains silent". In other words, this source makes it quite clear that a person whose dead lies before him, will be held in violation of kevod ha-met if he continues to attend to his other religious duties, even though he is not currently engaged in performing any specific duty related to the deceased. Kevod ha-met, in other words, takes clear precedence, according to Semahot, over all other obligations.
[16] Bavli, Berakhot, 19b. Compare Tosefta, Berakhot 2:10.
[17] That is to say, a prohibited mixture of linen and wool. See Lev. 19:19.
[18] At first blush it is not quite clear what exactly is the claim attributed to Rav. Should the question "What is the reason?" be considered as part of Rav's speech, or as an intervention on behalf of the s'tam? If the latter is the case, then the answer to it, along with the general principle concerning all profanations of God's name, might be claimed not to be an amoraic ruling at all - in which case the argument of this entire Section would lose much of its force. The question is, of course, not what Rav actually said, but the framer of this particular sugya understands Rav's statement to have been. It is clear from both the form and content of the meitivi-type interrogation of Rav's ruling that follows, that Rav is attributed the entire speech. First, the term meitivi is exclusively reserved by the Bavli to transgenerational objections. If before the first objection is raised, the s'tam can be said to have grounded Rav's assertion by means of a tannaitic principle, the term meitivi would have been quite inappropriate. Second, all five tannaitic sources cited in objection to Rav seem directed specifically against the latter, rather than the first part of his speech. I take it, therefore, that the entire passage is attributed to Rav and subjected, in its entirety, to the meitivi-type confrontations that follow.
[19] In talmudic Aramaic the word s'tam frequently denotes an anonymous (tannaitic) halakhic ruling. It is now used in the secondary literature as short hand for the anonymous framer/narrator of an amoraic sugya. In what follows I shall refer to "the Bavli", the Gemara", "the framer of the sugya" and "the s'tam" interchangeably.
[20] All five of them not only register halakhic edicts that contradict Rav by allegedly proving that in order to show respect certain rules of the Torah are superseded, but all but one concern superseding rules of the Torah related directly to graves, graveyards and funerals. One is again left with the distinct impression, created earlier by the insertion of the Tosefta passage ahead of Rav's ruling but not easy to prove, that behind these particular tannaitic rulings lurks a general tannaitic viewpoint founded on some form of analogy between respect for the living and the dead.
[21] Because it crosses a grave.
[22] See also Minor Tractate, Semahot 4:14. The reason given there for joining "the people" even if they chose the impure path, is "mipnei kevod ha-Shem" (out respect for God!). Most commentators, however, amend the text to read: "mipnei kevod ha-Am" (out of respect for the people). See also Yerushalmi, Nazir vii 56a and below ftn. 41 and text.
[23] A field or place considered impure only by Scribal injunction because the grave or graves it is known to have once contained can no longer be located. The particular type of bet ha-p'ras referred to here, is a grave which has been plowed over, so that bones may be scattered about.
[24] Anything that overshadows.
[25] In which case the impurity it overshadows does not remain contained within it.
[26] For other citations of this tannaitic saying see: Bavli, Shabbat 81b, 94b, Eruvin 41b, Megila 3b, Menahot 37b and Yerushalmi, Berakhot iii 6b. For a somewhat different rendition, see: Yerushalmi, Nazir vii 56a, Kilayim ix 32a. As for the saying itself. The Hebrew reads: "Great is human dignity she-dohe et lo ta'ase she-ba-Torah". The Soncino translates: "since it overrides a negative precept of the Torah", implying that the tanna indicates that human dignity overrides but only one negative precept, neglecting, however, to say which one. But the Hebrew wording of the saying and some of its usages elsewhere, especially in the Yerushalmi (as we shall see shortly), suggest that the saying praises human dignity for overriding not a negative precept, but any negative precept of the Torah.
[27] And thus rendering it applicable in practice only to Scribal decrees.
[28] In that he stood to lose more from interrupting his own work than the other for the loss of his animal.
[29] A nazirite who is also a priest.
[30] Because those things must be done at specific times and cannot be postponed.
[31] A met mitzva is an unclaimed body to which no one else is available to attend. The term literally means "(the burial of) a dead which is a religious obligation".
[32] Following a brief discussion of various halakhic technicalities related to the Mishna's specific rulings, the Gemara, on fol. 18a, launches a lengthy, four-page discussion of various forms and aspects of the notion of respect. The opening statement expressly, if incidentally associates, by means of a clever midrashic wordplay, one's duty to partake in a funeral procession with the notion of kavod (by juxtaposing Prov. 19:17 and 14:31 while substituting melave (to accompany, to partake in a funeral procession) for malve (to make a loan) in the former.) The remark is not addressed to the Mishna explicitly, however, but for students of the text who have asked themselves this question an answer is certainly insinuated. The opening statement is attributed to "Rahva says in the name of R. Yehuda". Interestingly, an early, gaonic citation of this saying attributes it to "R. Yehuda says in the name of Rav". See: Sheiltot de-rav Ahai Gaon (Jerusalem: Mossad Harav Kook, 1986), Bereishit, xiv.
[33] I say almost intact because it turns out in the end at least to exclude Scribal prohibitions, and the two Torah-based exceptions. More on this below.
[34] This impression is further corroborate by the fact that it is virtually impossible to square the Mishna with Rav's ruling by the tactics applied to the five other conflicting texts. The exemption granted by the Mishna cannot be limited to Scribal edicts because it explicitly mentions tefilin, and for the same reason cannot be written off as stating an exception expressly proscribed by Scripture.
[35] This in itself constitutes a serious problem for any antitraditionalist interpretation of talmudic discourse. How can anyone who appears never to discard an earlier source be at all considered an antitraditionalist? At this point, suffice it to say that there is a difference between being, or acting as an antitraditionalist, and describing, or relating to oneself as one. The passage we are dealing with from Bavli, Berakhot, as we have already seen, seems to offer a good example of an unreported antitraditionalist move, in which the Gemara clearly sides with an amoraic opinion that appears to contradict the very Mishna it is discussing.
[36] Of all the eitivei confrontations recorded by the Bavli, only three explicitly address the question to the tannaitic source under consideration, and do so in exactly the same words as does the s'tam in Berakhot 19b. See Bavli, Eruvin 50a; Hulin 123b and 124a. To recall, as opposed to confrontations of the meitivi variety, eitivei transgenerational challenges are polemic moves attributed to specific, named parties rather than to the anonymous s'tam (see ftn. 7 above). As explained above, these sugyot are less telling of the attitudes of their framers than those in which it is they who perform the questioning.
[37] Two such reading come to mind immediately. One is to understand the s'tam's queries as queries regarding Rav's interpretation of the five tannaitic texts. Their premise being that an amora could not have contradicted explicit tannaitic rulings, and that whenever he seems to do so, he must have read them differently. Thus construed the s'tam is asking how would Rav account for the fact that his principle was apparently not applied in these cases? One good reason for doubting such an interpretation is that two of the three non-midrashic tannaitic sources are reinterpreted on the authority of amoraim who functioned much later than Rav. It seems quite clear that the s'tam's questions are directed at the tannaitic sources themselves rather than at Rav's possible understanding of them. A different, and far more plausible traditionalist reading of the s'tam's repeated question, was urged upon me privately by Daniel Boyarin. On such a reading the question "Why is this so?" is understood as a form of modus tollens argumentation: If Rav's principle is true, why is it ignored by the tannaitic rulings - it follows, therefore, that it cannot be true. This is a perfectly reasonable construal of the question when the five meitivi confrontations are treated in isolation. As we shall see, such a reading loses much of its force when placed in a slightly wider interpretative context.
[38] The principle is cited and applied five times in the Bavli - Shabbat 81b, 94b, Eruvin 41b, Megila 3b, Menahot 37b - in order to justify infringements upon a variety of decrees in the name of respect for others. In all five cases the decrees involved are undeniably Scribal.
[39] The term here is kevod ha-rabim - the dignity of the many, or the majority - rather than kevod ha-beriyot - human dignity (lit. the dignity of people). Despite the verbal difference the two phrases are synonymous. See below ftn. 41.
[40] Several commentators on the Yerushalmi, clearly uncomfortable with the idea that a priest may be allowed to defile himself merely in order not to offend the people he is walking with, have tended to amend the beraita by supplying ulterior religious motives for the excursion. See, for example, comments by both the Pnei Moshe and Mar'eh Panim (both attributed to the eighteenth-century R. Moshe Margalit d. 1881) and Perush me-Ba'al Sefer Haredim (attributed to the sixteenth-century R. Eliezer Azkari d. 1601). To recall, the version cited by the Bavli reads: "If they have buried the body and are returning, and there are two ways open to them etc.".
[41] The term "human dignity" (kevod ha-briyot) employed in the Bavli's version and "dignity of the many" (kevod ha-rabim) used here are interchangeable (see above, ftn. 39) and possibly owe their origin to a scribal error (written in an abbreviated format, common in manuscript editions of talmudic texts, כבוד הרבי' and כבוד הברי' are easily confused). In any event, the version recapitulated almost verbatim in Yerushalmi, Nazir vii 56a, uses kevod ha-briyot. There is no question that the meta-halakhic principle attributed by the Yerushalmi on all three occasions to R. Zeira is the same as the one confronted with that of Rav by Bavli, Berakhot 19b.
[42] As we shall see shortly, the third mention of R. Zeira's principle in the Yerushalmi occurs in connection with the case most intimately associated with Rav's ruling, namely, that of discovering mixed kinds in public. As one would expect, commentators committed to harmonizing the two talmudim, have done their utmost to interpret that occurrence of R. Zeira's principle in keeping with that of the Bavli.
[43] Throughout the book, I use terms such as "existence and "matter of fact" in the literary, and not necessarily in the historical sense of the terms. Within the world of talmudic discourse, its persona dramatis and its history, as they are constructed by the Yerushalmi, such a faction identifies itself by name and by offering a direct answer to an explicit question. Whether such a faction, holding these views ever existed is another matter entirely.
[44] Cf. R. Moshe Margalit's Mar'eh Ha-Panim.
[45] In all, there are seven such rulings in the Yerushalmi. Two in favor of a position attributed to Rav - Yerushalmi, Kilayim ix 32a, Eruvin viii 25c; three in favor of the views of R. Shim'on b. Lakish - Hagiga ii 78c, and twice in Gitin vii 48c; one in favor of Shmuel - Horayot i 45d; and one in favor of R. Yossi b. Hanina - Nida iii 50c. Significantly, all four are amoraim of the first and second generation. More significantly, the latter three are never granted the special transitional tannaitic status granted to Rav on occasion by the Bavli (see below ftn. 59).
[46] See also Yerushalmi, Eruvin viii 25b. The same ruling, likewise attributed to Rav, is cited by the Bavli and also confronted with some of the same tannaitic material in: Bavli, Shabbat 64b (twice) and 146b, Beitza 9a and Avoda Zara 12a-b. As we shall see, the Bavli's treatment of these materials is, again, very different.
[47] The source is Tosefta, Kilayim 5:24.
[48] In his commentary to Tosefta, Kilayim 5:24, Saul Lieberman explains that because wool was frequently dyed black, a linen garment with a visible black hem would look like mixed kinds and is therefore prohibited for appearances' sake.
[49] Presumably, because they are only used in the privacy of one's home.
[50] The source is Tosefta, Avoda Zara 7:3. But compare Bavli, Avoda Zara 12a.
[51] See previous ftn.
[52] The source is Mishna, Hulin 2:9. The Bavli, however, passes it over without noting its discrepancy with Rav's ruling. The Tosafot (Bavli, Hulin 41a), who tend normally to harmonize as far as possible all seemingly conflicting talmudic texts, are forced to admit that the two talmudim probably disagree about the precise meaning of this mishna.
[53] Apparently collecting blood in this manner was practiced by heretics at the time. Interestingly, the original Mishna has Sadducees for heretics (minim).
[54] But compare Bavli, Shabbat 64b-65a.
[55] The first, unproblematic part of the beraita is Mishna, Eruvin 8:10, the additional last clause is a beraita cited again in Yerushalmi, viii 25b.
[56] Just as it is prohibited to transport goods from one domain to another on the Sabbath, so one is not allowed to pour water from one's yard into the street. The halakha, however, calculates the amount of water normally disposed of per day as the amount contained in a four-cubit deep drain. With such a drain, water pouring in at one end would in fact not reach the other (but would 'push out' other water that was there prior to the Sabbath). None the less, it prohibited for appearances' sake.
[57] Here, the precise formulation of the Yerushalmi is: "All these (mishnayot) contradict Rav, and they have no existence" (ve-let lehon kiyyum). The "and" is ambiguous and could be taken to denote a conjunction or conditional with equal viability. The formulation of the same proposition in Eruvin 35b is somewhat less ambiguous: "And Bar Kapra taught that if no one is present it is permitted. This contradicts Rav and has no validity (existence), for Rav says: "All that is prohibited for appearance's sake etc.". The implication is that Bar Kapra's ruling is null and void because Rav thought differently.
[58] The precise wording of this recurring Yerushalmi formulation is ve-let lahon kiyyum: and they have no existence, basis, ground. In modern parlance we would say: they are declared null and void. There is, however, a tendency among some philologists to soften the blow as it were. Thus, for example, M. Sokoloff, Dictionary of Jewish Palestinian Aramaic (Ramat Gan: Bar Ilan, 1990) renders the phrase: "and they have no answer". I find his translation wanting because it takes the absence of kiyyum to be a feature not of the six tannaitic sources but of the contradiction between them and the ruling attributed to Rav - in which case the sentence should have been in the singular: "All of these (beraitot) are in disagreement with Rav, and it has no answer".
[59] The idea that Rav tanna u-palig, that he enjoys transitional tannaitic status and may therefore dispute a mishna, is applied throughout the Bavli on five occasions. The Yerushalmi, on the other hand, makes no mention of such a principle as far as I can tell. However, even in the Bavli Rav special status is referred to only as a last resort. Thus, for example, on four separate occasions positions attributed to Rav are declared problematic by the Bavli as a result of meitivi challenges to them from tannaitic sources. (The talmudic term is teyuvta de-Rav.) In none of these cases is the problem resolved by resorting to Rav's alleged license to dispute tannaitic authority, and the difficulty is dealt with by other means. See Bavli, Shabbat 40a; Bava Metzia 107a; Menahot 5a; Bekhorot 55a.
[60] See above ftn. 58.
[61] Bavli, Shabbat 64b (twice) and 146b, Beitza 9a and Avoda Zara 12a-b.
[62] Because the person would then not necessarily appear to be going to, or to have come from, the place of forbidden worship.
[63] The Hebrew phrase is: "im eino nir'e", which is ambiguous, as the Bavli will be quick to point out, translating equally well as "if he is not seen" and "if he does not seem (to be bowing).
[64] In doing so the Yerushalmi reformulates the conditional clause so as to avoid any misunderstanding, in place of the Tosefta's u-be-makom she-eino nir'e (and where he is not seen), the Yerushalmi submits im haya be-makom tzanua (if he was in a secluded place). Thus construed, Rav's view flatly contradicts these earlier teachings which, as we have seen, are subsequently dismissed.
[65] The Bavli achieves this by a subtle change of phrase substituting for the Tosefta's u-be-makom she-eino nir'e (and in a place where he is not seen) the ambiguous phrase: ve-im eino nir'e (if he is not seen).
[66] Pp. 76-88.
[67] Mishna, Eduyot 5:6-7 and Bavli, Bava Metzia 59a-b respectively.
[68] The tannaitic origin of this saying is the Sifra to Lev. 10:1, where, as in all its later citations, it comes accompanied with a typical story about a student of R. Eliezer b. Hyrqanus who apparently issued halakhic rulings not far from his master's place of residence. Hearing of this, Eliezer predicted that he would not last the weekend, and indeed by the end of the Sabbath he was dead. see also Bavli, Eruvin 63a; Yerushalmi, Shvi'it vi 36c and Gittin i 43c. Such arrogance does not merit capitol punishment, of course, but is only punishable by death by the Hand of God.
[69] Bavli, Sanhedrin 100a. For a useful anthology of talmudic and post-talmudic sources related to these issues see H. Ben-Menahem, N. Hecht. Sh. Wosner (eds.) Controversy and Dialogue in Halakhic Sources (Hebrew) (Tel-Aviv: Alfil, 1991), Vol. I, Ch. 11.
[70] Cf. Bavli, Berakhot 27b and Minor Tractate Kalla Rabati 2:15.
[71] For the clearest statement of this principle see Bavli, Shevu'ot 31a. For an explicit employment of Rav's principle to justify it, see Bavli, Eruvin 63a.
[72] Bavli, Berakhot 20a. The lesson is made explicit by a pun. After being fined R. Ada is said to have asked the woman her name. "Matun", she replied. "Matun, Matun", he muttered, "is worth four-hundred Zuzim". "Matun" is, on the one hand, Hebrew for deliberate, moderate, measured, and, on the other, resembles the word for two-hundred in Aramaic. “Had I been more cautious”, he mused, “I would have saved having to pay”. The lesson, then, is not to refrain from ripping off a person's inappropriate attire, or from contradicting one's master's rulings, but not to be zealous about it; to think twice, consider alternatives, and always take a second look.
[73] Eruvin 63a tells of Ravina, disciple of R. Ashi, who, in the presence of his teacher, noticed a person publicly violating a rabbinic injunction (by tying his ass to the trunk of a palm on the Sabbath). Rather than wait for his master to respond, Ravina is said to have shouted to the man, and getting no reaction from him declared him excommunicated. "In doing so was I acting disrespectfully to you?", he asked R. Ashi. No, answered his teacher, in these cases we say: "'There is no wisdom nor understanding nor counsel against the Lord'; wherever a profanation of God's name is involved no respect is paid (even) to a teacher". (Interestingly, according to Berakhot 19b, Rav's principle may not be expected to apply to such cases of a rabbinic prohibition. See also Bavli, Moed Katan 17a.
[74] On the citation of the incident concerning the Passover feast introduced by Todos of Rome, the s'tam remarks that R. Yehoshua referred specifically to "our Mishna", and this particular incident is related only in a beraita. "Are there no such cases in the Mishna itself", he asks, clearly implying the greater significance of the Mishna in comparison to other tannaitic sources. In view of the fact that a page later the Gemara will tacitly discriminate again between the Mishna and beraitot, allowing the former to be contradicted by Rav while fastidiously harmonizing Rav with the latter, I find this remark highly significant.
[75] The Babylonian Talmud: Tractate Berakot - Translated into English for the First Time, with Introduction, Commentary, Glossary and Indices by The Rev. A. Cohen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1921), p. 125, ftn. 3.
[76] Pp. 156-8.
[77] Tractate Uktzin of Order Tahorot is notorious for its complexity, as are the disputations between Rav and Shmuel, R. Yehuda's teachers. For the former See Bavli, Horayot 13b.
[78] This refers not to Uktzin but to Mishna Tahorot 2:1, also of Order Tahorot.
[79] Mishna, Uktzin 2:1.
[80] Or by thirteen different methods. The implication is the same: our command of the world of learning is far superior to that of the generation of R. Yehuda.
[81] On occasions of mourning and public and private fasting one always removes one's shoes. At times of drought R. Yehuda, then, despite his inferior learning, would only have to make the fist sign of self humiliation for his plea to be answered.
[82] The entire exchange appears almost verbatim in Bavli, Ta'anit 24b and Sanhedrin 106b.